字幕列表 影片播放 列印英文字幕 (intro music) Hi, I'm Stephan Schmid. I'm teaching at the Humboldt University in Berlin in Germany, and today, I want to talk about Descartes's famous cogito argument. Even if you have never heard of the name "cogito argument" before, or of Descartes, you might have encountered the argument itself. It is nothing other than the famous philosophical insight "I think, therefore, I am," or in Latin, "cogito ergo sum." This argument has become so popular that it has even become the subject of jokes. Consider this one. Descartes walks into a bar. The bartender walks up to him and says, "Hey, would you care for a drink?" Descartes replies, "Hmm, I think not." And poof! He disappears. Now, I admit that this joke is probably not the best joke ever, but Descartes's cogito argument, to which this joke appeals, is definitely pretty cool. The most exciting feature of Descartes's cogito argument is not the argument itself, though. It can actually already be found in Aristotle and Saint Augustine. It is rather the philosophical question that Descartes tried to answer with it. But who was this guy Descartes, anyway? And what is this question that the cogito argument is supposed to answer? Rene Descartes was a French philosopher of the seventeenth century. He was dissatisfied with the philosophy of his time, which was dominated by scholastic philosophy. The scholastics saw to answer highly abstract philosophical questions mainly on the basis of Aristotle's teaching. Descartes was dissatisfied with this kind of philosophy because he considered their highly abstract disputes pointless and futile, and also unable to accommodate the results of the rising mechanistic physics, which sought to account for natural phenomena in mathematical terms. On account of his dissatisfaction with the philosophy of his day, Descartes came to think that the philosophy was in need of a fundamental reboot, a completely fresh start. This is surely a nice idea, but how do you build a new philosophical system? Well, maybe it's just in a way we usually build new and stable things, such as houses and monuments: just by building them up on a strong and stable foundation. Yet, what would serve as an appropriate firm foundation upon which to build a new philosophical theory? Descartes was convinced that nothing could do the job better than our most certain beliefs that is, the things that we can really be sure are true. Let us now finally turn to Descartes's attempt to establish a firm foundation for his new philosophy. He carries out his attempt most extensively in his "Meditations On First Philosophy." As we said, he wants to find absolutely certain and unshakable beliefs that he can build his new philosophy upon. The method that Descartes suggests has become known as "Descartes' radical doubt." The main idea is to subject all our beliefs to radical doubt, and then see which of them can withstand such doubt and hence be accepted as absolutely certain. As the application of this method reveals, there is indeed a huge difference between the things that we in fact take ourselves to be certain about and the things we may justifiably do so. Just consider the following examples. You're doubtlessly pretty certain that you're watching a video right now, or that you have brushed your teeth this morning, or that two plus two equals four. Yet are you really justified in being so certain? Descartes thinks that after having employed his method of radical doubt, you will have to admit that you are not. Indeed, there are only very few beliefs that pass Descartes's test of radical doubt. Can you be really certain that you are watching a video right now? No, you cannot. After all you could just as well be dreaming. The same holds about your beliefs that you brushed your teeth this morning. And most shockingly, perhaps, not even mathematical beliefs escape Descartes's radical doubt, for how can we be sure that two plus two equals four, say? True, we have often convinced ourselves that we get a collection of four objects if we unite two collections of two objects, but what ensures that we did not err every time we convinced ourselves of this? Perhaps there is an evil demon, or a wicked neuroscientist, who constantly manipulates our thoughts by systematically distracting us when we try to verify our mathematical beliefs. As these considerations show, Descartes's method of radical doubt leaves hardly any belief unaffected. But there is hope. Descartes argues that there is at least one thing that we cannot doubt and which we can be absolutely certain about. This is the fact that when we doubt, we cannot doubt that we doubt or think, for doubting is just a form of thinking. But when we can be sure that we think, we can be equally sure that we exist while we are thinking, for if indeed we can be sure that we are thinking, there has to be something that does the thinking, and we are the something, you and I. It is, hence, here that we finally arrive at Descartes' famous cogito argument, "I think, therefore, I am." The cogito argument then assures us of the fact that there is at least one thing that is impossible to doubt and is thus absolutely certain. This is the fact that we exist while we think. And this is precisely the unquestionable fact that can figure as the unshakable and firm foundation which Descartes has been looking for in order to build his new philosophical system upon. The prospect of building a whole world view upon the certainly that we exist while we think must strike you as not very promising. Given that we can only be certain that we exist while we think, how can we ever know, as we seem to, that we live on a planet we share with human beings and other animals and which orbits the sun. And how can you know that two plus two equals four, or that you are watching a video? It is indeed a long road for Descartes to restore our certainly in our common sense beliefs, and many of these beliefs have to be abandoned along the way. Amongst those are our commonly accepted beliefs that materials things are really colored or have other sensory properties like tastes, smells, and sounds. It takes Descartes the whole rest of his six meditations to walk down this road and restore our confidence in our beliefs of mathematical truths and the existence of the outer world. It would take us hours to carefully reenact all the steps. However, in order to get a rough grasp of Descartes's procedure, it will be worthwhile to reconstruct just one step that Descartes takes in order to extend the stock of beliefs that we can justifiably be certain about. The method Descartes employs for extending our certain beliefs consists in squeezing out the certainties he has already arrived at. Actually, we have already encountered this method, for Descartes's cogito argument is such a way of squeezing out a certain belief or idea from another. After all, the cogito argument is an argument, that is, a transition or an inference from one belief to another. The unshakable belief that this argument starts out from is the belief that we are thinking when we are doubting, and we arrive at this certainty just by observing that whatever we might doubt, we cannot doubt that we doubt when we doubt. Now, the cogito argument takes this certainty and squeezes out the new certainty that we cannot only be sure that we think when we doubt but also that we exist when we think. And it is exactly this newly gained certainty of our existence which the cogito argument provides us that Descartes squeezes next. In a famous passage of his second meditation, he writes, "I am, I exist - that is certain. "But for how long? "For as long as I am thinking. "I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing "that thinks; that is, I am a mind, or intelligence "or intellect or reason. "But for all that, I am a thing which is real "and which truly exists. "But what kind of a thing? "As I have just said - a thinking thing." As becomes plain here, Descartes immediately squeezes out further information about his nature from the certain belief that he exists while he thinks. As a result, Descartes cannot only know with certainty that he exists, but also that he is a thinking thing, a thing capable of thinking. This is still not a lot, though. At this stage, Descartes can only be ensured of the fact that he is a thinking thing, and it is still an open question whether he also has a body, as we usually suppose. If you are puzzled now, or even afraid that you cannot know whether you really have a body, that you really are watching this video, or that you really have brushed your teeth this morning, the only comfort I can give you is that Descartes at least thought that it can be proved that we can be certain that we have a body and that our senses, by and large, assure us of the existence of other corporeal things, even though they systematically deceive us about their nature. And this can be proved by further squeezing out our clear and distinct idea of ourselves as a thinking thing. If this promise is not enough to give you comfort, then there is only one last advice I can give you. Go and get a copy of Descartes's "Meditations On First Philosophy," and start reading his third meditation. Subtitles by the Amara.org community
B1 中級 美國腔 哲學 - 歷史。笛卡爾論證 [高清] (PHILOSOPHY - History: Descartes' Cogito Argument [HD]) 43 12 耀梅林 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日 更多分享 分享 收藏 回報 影片單字