Placeholder Image

字幕列表 影片播放

  • last time I defined a category for you, and explained that the most important

  • features of a category composability and identity and then

  • I started talking about the most important example of a category that we

  • use in programming, that's the category of types and functions, right. so in

  • programming we have types and functions.

  • But the model for types and functions is really sets, sets and

  • functions between sets, right. So I mean every time you design a language you have

  • to provide semantics for the language right?

  • What does it mean, certain things in language and a lot of languages are

  • defined using so-called operational semantics i mean the ones who actually

  • have semantics, right.

  • There are very few of them, none of the major ones. But they sort of like, have part of its semantics

  • defined right? And there are two ways of defining semantics one is by telling

  • how this thing executes right, so it's called operational semantics, because you're

  • defining operations of of the language. You know how one expression or

  • statement can be transformed into another simpler one and so on. And

  • the other is called denotational semantics where you actually map it into

  • some other area that you understand and in particular the most interesting

  • way of mapping this is into mathematics, right so you build a mathematical model you say "this statement in the

  • "language or this construct in the language corresponds some mathematical

  • "thing." and this mathematical thing for instance for types is a set of values. For

  • functions, it's a function between sets. Ok, that's why it's so important and that's why I

  • will just talk about type sometimes and sometimes I will say Set, sometimes i

  • will say type because I have this semantics in mind

  • Ok? So what is important is that a function in programming, especially when

  • you are considering you know imperative programming it's not exactly the same as

  • the function in mathematics right so we have to like be more specific by

  • "function between sets" we really understand something that in programming

  • would be called pure function right? And it will be a pure function and a total

  • function because a mathematical function is defined for every argument

  • not just for some arguments right? This is like the major source of problems in

  • programming that we have these partial functions, functions are defined for some

  • arguments and for other arguments they explode, right? I mean if they throw

  • exception that and then we catch this exception it's fine right but quite often

  • they don't they just

  • destroy the computer, explode and stuff. So, a total function is defined for all its

  • arguments right and these arguments are taken from some type so like if it's a

  • function on integers it has to be defined for all integers right? And

  • it's a pure function and how can you tell if a function is pure? So I have this test

  • for a purity of a function: a function is pure if you can memoise it which means

  • ah you know you can turn it into a lookup table right? Because for every

  • value of an argument it should return one particular value right? And you can

  • just remember this value, okay, you call this function once it evaluates it and then

  • you can remember the next time you do a lookup into a table right? So if you have

  • like you know, types that are finite that only have a finite number of

  • elements like boolean right then it's really easy to tabulate them,

  • functions on characters if it's just ASCII characters, they are really easy to tabulate

  • right, all these functions like `isAlpha`, you know, or `isPrintable`, they

  • are all actually tabulated, so they are very fast.

  • Now functions on, let's say integers or strings, they usually cannot be

  • tabulated right but that's only a problem because of resources right? If we

  • had infinite resources we could tabulate it. So ask yourself the question "can I

  • actually memoise this function?" and for instance a function like `getChar` cannot

  • be memoised, right? You call it once and then you say "Oh, it returned 'h', good.

  • "I'll just remember it and from now on whenever somebody calls function getChar I will return 'h'

  • "and that's it". No, you can't do this, right, so this is not a pure function. Now of course

  • you might say "okay, but how can you program using only pure functions" right?

  • We need things like side effects

  • So all this stuff can be described on top of pure functions, but

  • what we really want is to get to the bottom of the abstraction like what is the

  • lowest level (or the highest level of abstraction depending on how you look at it) right?

  • so what is the atom, what are the building blocks

  • what are the simplest building blocks from which we can build more

  • complex stuff right? Using again the same idea of composability so first we want

  • to decompose the problem, get to the little blocks at the bottom, and then

  • recompose stuff from there.

  • So when we are decomposing this idea of using procedures and data types and so

  • on, we eventually get to the bottom and that's pure functions. So on top of your

  • functions we can be building more complex stuff, including things like I/O

  • So now that we have this category of types and functions, right and I talked a little

  • bit about this, now let me expand on functions, because functions are very

  • interesting, there's much more to know about functions than we usually consider

  • right? So they are really interesting beasts. Even these pure

  • functions right? Total pure functions. We have to look at them from a

  • slightly different perspective- from a perspective of how we can use them

  • as morphisms in our category right? The category Set

  • which contains sets and functions between sets.

  • So functions are defined in mathematics as special kinds of relations

  • ok what's a relation? Relation is, you know, take two sets they have elements

  • right. Now we're talking about set as in set theory, not as a category. In a category

  • won't be able to look at elements, but in set theory we can look at elements right? A relation is

  • just a subset of pairs of elements

  • So it's just a pairing of things, we say this element in a relation

  • with this element, ok? And again as I explained we are using our brains to

  • understand these things and here we are like talking about relationships so

  • this is, you know our relationship frame, talking about social

  • interactions in mathematics.

  • Yes you have a question > Does the relation have to be total?

  • In general? No.

  • We're just talking about general relations in mathematics right?

  • So we say ok, this person is in a relation with this person and they are, lets say friends.

  • So this guy's a friend of this guy maybe this guy's not a friend of this

  • guy so the relation doesn't have to be symmetric you know? So, let me define a

  • relation okay?

  • First of all what is a set of pairs? A set of pairs in mathematics is called a

  • Cartesian product, right? So we have two sets, S1 and S2, and we can do

  • a Cartesian product of it so all elements from one set are paired with

  • all possible evidence from the other set so the set of all pairs forms the

  • Cartesian product. Now we take a subset of this Cartesian product, we just pick

  • some pairs, randomly or not, you know, if they are meaningful. We just

  • pick a subset and any subset of this Cartesian product is a relation by

  • definition that's a relation ok? So there are no other requirements, just a subset of

  • the Cartesian product, that's a relation.

  • So in this sense relation does not have a directionality, right, whereas functions

  • functions have direction functions are these arrows so this is one of the most

  • important things to understand, that functions have some kind of

  • directionality. So what kind of condition do we have to impose on the

  • relation for it to become a function? And in a relation we can have this element

  • you know, pick an element in this set, it can be in relation with many elements in this

  • other set right? And vice versa, an element from set can be in relation

  • (well okay I'm drawing, putting these arrows in this direction). So many elements from set S1 can be

  • in relation with a single element in set 2, or one element from set 1

  • can be in relation with many elements from set 2, both are ok for every

  • relation. One of them is not okay for functions.

  • (I need an eraser)

  • I'm not gonna use my hand!

  • Which one is bad for a function? The top one right? One element, one argument of a

  • function cannot be mapped into a bunch of things. It has to be mapped to one thing

  • ok? It's still ok for multiple arguments to be mapped into the same value for a

  • function, but not the other way. So that's where the directionality comes from. Last,

  • we want to be considering total functions for our category right? So this

  • whole set has to be mapped. All elements of this set must be mapped into something in this other set

  • Ok? However it's not true that all the elements from this set have to

  • counter, you know, have to come from this set. So this could be a subset that's being mapped

  • Ok? Now these things have names so let me name these things for future reference

  • so that we can talk about them easily. So if you have a function f,

  • (so this is like a graph of the function f) this is called the domain

  • of a function, right? The domain of the function is just this set from

  • which we have started, the whole set.

  • that's its domain. This set is called the codomain.

  • And this subset that was obtained by mapping the whole domain is usually

  • called the image of the function.

  • Ok?

  • So functions are not symmetric in this way, you

  • see? This is the whole set, this could be a subset. Multiple elements can be

  • merged into one element but not vice versa.

  • So there is this directionality and this directionality is very important

  • That's a very important intuition about functions, and this is

  • not only an intuition about functions because later we'll see that in

  • category theory also we have all kinds of other mappings, we have mappings between

  • categories called functors, we have mappings between functors which are called natural transformations

  • and so on. All these mappings have the same kind of

  • directionality, ok? And the simplest way to understand this directionality

  • is asking "is the function invertible?". Like, if I go from here to here is it

  • possible to go back?

  • And usually it's not. So if there is a function f from some A to B, you

  • know, there isn't always a function that goes the other way around, that is the

  • inverse of this function. How do we define an inverse of a function?

  • Well, if you have a function that goes from A to B, and I will be

  • using this notation that is just taken from Haskell,

  • So f is a function, double colon means "this is the type of function",

  • the type of function, it goes from a to b. Alright so this is set A, set B, type a type b.

  • Ok? So this function is invertible if there is another function that goes in

  • the other direction, from b to a. That's the inverse of this one, what does

  • it mean? It means that g after f equals id.

  • Ok? So if you first go f to B and then go back from B to A using g, you should end up

  • in the same, exactly the same point. So if you have an x here, x maps it to

  • some y here and then you apply g to y, you should get back to x ok? That

  • means the inverse, ok, but we can compose them two ways right? So g after f is one,

  • but there's also a composition f after g and this one also has to be an identity.

  • So we go g first and then f, and you should end up at the same point ok? So this makes it

  • symmetric. So a function that's invertible is automatically symmetric ok?

  • And the function that is invertible is called isomorphism.

  • So this is the definition of isomorphism and notice an interesting thing:

  • this is in the language of categories.

  • Maybe with a little bit of additional notation, if f goes from A to B and g

  • goes from B to A then this is an identity in which object? In A. Right? So

  • Now let's forget about this picture and say A, B, this is f, this is g.

  • Ok? So g after f, I'll get identity on a. and then f after g, is the same as

  • identity on b. Okay, and I have written this in categorical language, I'm not talking

  • anymore about elements, right? Here I was talking about elements of sets, I

  • don't need to. Okay? Now I can go back to categories and say "this is a definition

  • of isomorphism in any category". Not only in a category of sets, in any category because

  • it's expressed in terms of composition and identity, nothing else, right? So f is

  • an isomorphism if there exists a g with these properties

  • Ok?

  • So isomorphisms are great because isomorphisms, like, identify two

  • sets they say "this set really looks like this set", that there's like one to one

  • mapping between elements of these sets right? So that's, you know, if this is a two

  • element set and this is a two element set, you know I have a mapping between

  • these elements. That's great, right? For my purposes they are sort of like

  • identical right? It's not really identity, it's isomorphism, but I have an

  • identification between these two sets. So for finite sets you know an isomorphism

  • is just an identification of elements, this element corresponds to this, this

  • corresponds to this and so on,

  • one-to-one correspondence. For infinite sets, of course, this is a little bit more

  • complicated. For instance you can have a one-to-one correspondence between

  • natural numbers and even numbers.

  • y = 2x

  • even numbers. Or odd numbers

  • Right? These are functions that are invertible. Is that true?

  • No, but if this is a set of even numbers, right, so let's say this is a

  • set of even numbers (not the set of all numbers, just a set of even numbers) and this

  • is the set of all numbers, and then I have one-to-one correspondence between

  • even numbers and all numbers, right?

  • That's because they are infinite and for infinite sets you can do tricks like

  • these, but if this is a natural number and this is, say, you know

  • real numbers, right? Real numbers.

  • Now you know that there is no correspondence like this right? Do you know that?

  • There's a good argument, that [...]

  • But that's just a side remark, right. So just to make you aware of the fact that

  • isomorphisms kinda tell you that these two things are for some intents and purposes identical

  • But most functions are not isomorphisms, right?

  • Most in a sense of, I dunno, most functions that we deal with are not

  • isomorphisms and there are two reasons for a function not to be an isomorphism,

  • Ok? So you have to have good reasons not to be an isomorphism. One reason is because

  • the function can collapse elements of a set, right? So it takes multiple

  • multiple elements of this set are mapped to a single element of this set, so let me be

  • more precise here, just focus on one thing

  • so you have some x_1 and you have some x_2, and function f maps both of these elements to the same y.

  • Ok? For instance, let's see, a function `isEven`, which returns a boolean, right?

  • So `isEven` maps every even number into this one element of the boolean called true.

  • All even numbers are mapped to true, all odd numbers are mapped false so lots,

  • lots of numbers are mapped into one value. So we have this kind of gluing

  • going so that's one reason for this function not to be invertible. There's

  • another reason for it not to be invertible and that it doesn't–

  • that its image does not fill the whole codomain, right? So you have a function in which

  • No, so this is the codomain but there are some points here, this is the image

  • of function f, there are some points outside of the image that

  • just don't correspond to any x's here, right?

  • So if you would want to invert this function you would have to to create a

  • function g and what's the value of g on this point right? maybe you can invert

  • for these points you can say okay this x is mapped to this y

  • ok maybe I can invert it, if I don't have this gluing right? Then maybe I can invert it,

  • but I don't know what to do with this guy, what's should g be on this? No idea.

  • Yes? > Isn't it possible to have an inverse relation on this [...] or do we not care about those?

  • Yes, yes, yes and in fact, you know at some point people have this,

  • instead of inverting functions what you could say is that the counter image of

  • this y, right, it would

  • Ok, in this case, right, it will be some bunch of points here, right? And this bunch of

  • points that are mapped to the same point.

  • It's called a fibre ok? And fibration is a very interesting topic in category theory.

  • Because then you can build a set of fibers here and you can say "Okay, on

  • a set of fibres this thing is invertible". I'm getting really really ahead now, ok

  • So there are these two reasons for a non-invertibility, so I like to think of this

  • like a function, if you think of a function as something directional

  • something, a process that takes place in time, a function that's not invertible

  • is something that increases entropy, right? It boils an egg and you

  • cannot un-boil an egg, right? So these kind of things make, you know, make this thing

  • non-invertible. And it's very important because these two things, these two

  • phenomena here that make it non-invertible, they correspond to a very

  • interesting thought process that we use to solve problems.

  • This corresponds to abstraction, this means, you know "I really don't care which

  • "of these points I came from". I'm only interested in one property there, so I'm

  • abstracting, I'm throwing away some information about whether it was x_1 or

  • x_2 and I'm left with just one piece of information. For instance I'm throwing away

  • information about what was the exact number that I mapped, i'm just extracting the

  • information whether it was even or odd.

  • Ok? So I'm sifting information, right? And I cannot invert it, I cannot say "Oh, it

  • "was an even number so it must be two, must be zero." No, right I don't know how

  • I came to this conclusion, but I have abstracted a bunch of information and now

  • I have just this one piece of information that I care about.

  • Ok? So this is the process of abstraction. This on the other hand, is the process of

  • modelling, ok? I'm modeling this set inside this bigger set, or maybe it's not

  • bigger. right, but since it has this,

  • this environment, right. So I'm saying "okay I'm recognizing the pattern that's

  • "defined by this set inside this second set."

  • So I'm mapping it, so I'm sort of, like injecting this right here, right? This is some

  • stick figure or something, and I see the same stick figure here.

  • Ok? So you know this is maybe a human sitting in a cave, and this is the

  • shadow on the wall of the cave. I'm embedding it in here.

  • And I'm abstracting maybe also, right? Because this is a

  • three-dimensional guy, this is a two-dimensional shadow and doesn't

  • have, you know, so I'm doing both abstraction and modelling. And then

  • somebody comes and recognizes this

  • "Hey you just drew a person!"

  • Oh! The first human being drew the person on the wall and they are excited. So they

  • just discovered category theory.

  • Ok so mathematicians of course have names for these things, right? But they

  • their names are like the inverse what I described so, like, they say

  • "If a function does not collapse things then its called injective, or injection"

  • An injective function does not collapse

  • things ok? So if you have two different x's, x_1 and x_2, and you map them with a

  • function then you will always get y_1 and y_2, they will be different so if x_1 is

  • different from x_2 and

  • ok let me write fx_1 and fx_2. So if these guys are different, then these guys

  • are different too. Which means it's not collapsing anything, right?

  • It's just injecting the thing as is, right? The whole thing with all the

  • points in here get transported to this other set.

  • No shrinking, no forgetting, no abstraction so thats an injective function.

  • It just injects.

  • And this thing also they have a name for the opposite of this, namely, if the

  • function covers the whole codomain, right, the image is equal to the codomain, then

  • it's called surjective.

  • And that's from I don't know French or Latin "sur-" means "on" right so it's "onto".

  • It's a function onto the other. So this one is a counterexample for a

  • surjection right? That's not a surjection because it has this terra

  • incognita here. A surjection doesn't have this, a surjection covers the whole thing right?

  • And in particular in set theory, you know, if you have a function that's both

  • injective and surjective at the same time it's actually an isomorphism, you

  • can invert ok? So that's a good thing to know. But now you might say "Okay,

  • "so we know something about set theory, that there are injective functions and

  • "surjective functions". Now if we define this in terms of elements, right I said

  • elements here, right?

  • And surjected it means that for all ys in the second set, y

  • equals f_x right? There exists an x. For all y's there exists an x, that y is equal to f_x.

  • That's in terms of elements of a set. Like, there is no thing outside.

  • Every element that I pick in this set has a counter-image, ok? So I have

  • defined something in terms of elements. And now if I go to category theory, you know, the Set category,

  • how do I talk about injections and surjections, right? If I cannot look at the elements.

  • Turns out I can, but it's a tricky business because I have to express this

  • stuff now only in terms of morphisms, right, of other morphism so I have to,

  • like, turns out I have to talk about all the other objects in the category, all of

  • them, in order to define this one property.

  • And this is very very characteristic to category theory, if you want to

  • define a property of an object or an arrow, you define it with respect to

  • essentially everything else, ok? So this is a very holistic approach, right? You

  • cannot just focus on one little thing because no matter how good your

  • microscope is you cannot look inside this little point, right? Where a is, right?

  • And here's b. Because in category theory this is a point, here it's a big thing I can look at it

  • using a microscope, so if my microscopes don't work, maybe my

  • telescopes will work. I'll be looking at the whole universe and I will say

  • "this little guy is in a relationship with the universe" and the

  • relationship of this guy with the universe is such that I can say

  • something of this type, like it's sort of injective or surjective, except that in

  • category theory, we don't like Latin, ok? We use Greek. So instead of saying something

  • is surjective, you know "sur-", "onto" and in Greek it's "epi-", right?

  • so we'll say that something is surjective it's called "epic"

  • ok and something that's injective it's called "monic".

  • Or monomorphism, monic thingy, or monomorphism

  • and it's can be called epimorphism.

  • I'm getting outside of my area.

  • Or an epic morphism okay? So epimorphism and surjective function: it's

  • the same thing when you consider just set theory, right? And injective and

  • monic is the same in set theory. But these things are defined for any

  • category, so they are much more general. So how would we define this stuff, ok, let me

  • erase this maybe, we remember this, it's an easy thing.

  • How would we define, let's say an epimorphism? I think that's easier.

  • So we have a function from A to B, sorry not a function, a morphism,

  • ok but let's let's, first thing about the function but let's try to define

  • this property of a function that's surjective in such a way that we don't talk about elements.

  • Ok so first we'll start with a set, but we'll try to find the property of

  • a surjective function that can be expressed purely in terms of other functions

  • So let's first think aboutif it's not surjective what does it mean? If it's not

  • surjective it means that there are guys here that are not in the image, right? so

  • suppose that I take another function called g from this set, so this is my set A, this is my set B

  • let's say I take a set C, whatever set, right, and the function g from B to C. So

  • as you can see function g will have values for elements that are in this terra

  • incognita and also for these elements that are in the image of f, right? But if I

  • compose these two, and here's the trick, I have to talk about composition because

  • composition is the only thing i have at my disposal in a category. So I better

  • talk in terms of composition, right? So if I talk in terms of composition, if I

  • compose this function f with g then look what happens: this x will go inside the

  • image and g will take it to someso this is, lets say y, this is some z, right

  • So g after f will actually not probe this

  • terra incognita, right? Even though g maps everything, inside composition it will

  • actually only act on this, right? Inside the composition. Because it's acting on

  • y's and these y's were obtained by acting on x's using f.

  • That's how a composition of functions is defined in Set. Aha. So if I take two

  • such functions, g_1 let's say, and another function g_2, and these functions only

  • differ here, so g_1, maps this guy

  • into this point and g_2 maps this guy then g_1 is different from g_2 right?

  • They map points differently, or actually what i want to say is the same

  • point is mapped by g_1 and g_2 to something different, right?

  • That's the difference. The same point is mapped to different points, that means g_1

  • and g_2 are different functions. But if they only differ outside, in this halo, the

  • composition with f will be the same. So the composition g1 after f

  • will be the same as g_2 after f, even though g_1 is different from g_2. So

  • the converse of this is if for every g_1 and g_2

  • If g_1 after f equals g_2 after f

  • It follows that g_1 is equal to g_2

  • for every such combination then, I can say this function is surjective, right I'm

  • just like reversing the logic. If, for any object C and any pair of functions

  • g1 and g2 from B to C, if g_1 after f is the same as g_2 after f, then

  • g_1 must be equal to g_2. If this is true, then the function is surjective. And look at what

  • happened, now I have expressed this purely in terms of categorical terms

  • And maybe I should put one more, for every c for all c's, for all objects

  • c's for all morphisms g_1 g_2 that go from B to C if from g_1 f equals g_2 f

  • it follows that g_1 is equal to g_2, then this is an epimorphism. And this

  • definition will work for any category. In the category of Set, this is just exactly the

  • same as a surjective function, but in any category I can define something like

  • this because I'm only using composition. But notice that I'm using

  • quantifiers "for all". So I have to consider all objects in my category all

  • c's, and all possible pairs of morphisms from B to C, right? So I'm really,

  • really looking at the whole universe just to define this one property of f. And

  • the way to remember this property, one way of looking at this, is that if i have

  • this kind of relation it means that i can i can cancel something on the

  • right, it means if I have g_1 after f equals

  • g_2 after f, then I can cancel f. And what do I get? g_1 equals g_2. Right? This is this is

  • actually a good point for a break

last time I defined a category for you, and explained that the most important

字幕與單字

單字即點即查 點擊單字可以查詢單字解釋

A2 初級

類別理論 2.1:函數、外貌 (Category Theory 2.1: Functions, epimorphisms)

  • 40 5
    張嘉軒 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日
影片單字