Placeholder Image

字幕列表 影片播放

  • How can we grasp the concept of infinity? By understanding infinite sets.

  • Let's ease into this by starting with a simple question: how can you show that

  • you have the same number of fingers as toes? Most people

  • would say, "ten fingers, ten toes, done." That's fine, but it brings in

  • an unnecessary concept; the actual *counting* of fingers and toes.

  • I only asked why the two sets had the same size, not to

  • actually count them. How else can one answer the question? By making

  • a one-to-one correspondence between the toes and fingers,

  • that is, pair up each finger with exactly one toe.

  • This connection shows that the two sets have the same size without counting.

  • By the way, since most people cannot touch their toes, please

  • do not try this unsupervised.

  • Although this pairing process seems strange, you're actually

  • already familiar with it, especially when the two sets are large:

  • whether you're counting left shoes and right shoes, nuts and bolts,

  • front and rear bike tires, or brides and grooms at a mass wedding,

  • the numbers always match up because these objects come in pairs.

  • So how do we compare the size of infinite sets?

  • If there is a one-to-one matching between two infinite sets,

  • we think of them as the same size. Mathematicians use the word

  • "cardinality" to describe how big a set is, but we'll just use

  • the word "size".

  • For example, the set of positive integers has the same size

  • as the set of all non-zero integers. How is this possible since the

  • first set fits into the second? After you've matched the positive

  • integers together, don't all the leftovers suggest that the

  • second set has a larger size? In fact, the second set seems to be

  • twice as large as the first set since each positive integer has a

  • corresponding negative integer. But the two sets actually have the

  • same size. We see this by arranging the elements in the second

  • set differently. Although the order of the numbers seems strange,

  • you can see that every non-zero integer will eventually appear,

  • and so there is a correspondence between the two sets.

  • A more devious example involves rational numbers, fractions which are

  • the ratio of two integers. The claim is that the rational numbers

  • also have the same size as the positive integers. Again, how can this be?

  • Even between zero and one there are infinitely many rational

  • numbers, so how can these two sets have the same cardinality?

  • Place rationals on a grid where the numerator is the same on each row

  • and the denominator is the same on each column. Now start at 1/1 and follow

  • the path, touching each positive rational number.

  • The first few rationals we hit are 1, 2, 1/2, 1/3, 3, 4, 3/2, and 2/3.

  • Note that some of the numbers have been crossed out. For example,

  • 2/4 and 3/6 will be skipped over. That's OK because these numbers can

  • both be written in lowest form as 1/2. We want to pass through each fraction

  • exactly once so we eliminate these copies. The positive rationals

  • can thus be listed, so they have the same cardinality as the integers.

  • These ideas about the size of infinite sets were developed by

  • the German mathematician Georg Cantor. Everyone was surprised

  • by his ideas, including Cantor himself. When he realized that the set of points in

  • a square has the same size as the set of points on a line, his reaction

  • was “I see it, but I don’t believe it!”

  • While these ideas are considered mainstream by

  • today's mathematicians, they illicited different responses

  • from Cantor's contemporaries. Poincare considered his work a "grave disease" and Kronecker asserted

  • that Cantor was a "scientific charlatan", a "renegade",

  • and a "corrupter of youth". On the other hand,

  • David Hilbert strongly defended Cantor's ideas, declaring that

  • "No one shall expel us from the Paradise which Cantor has created."

  • These strong opinions seem more justified with the following

  • provocative question: Are there infinite sets which are NOT countable?

  • Such a set would be so big that we couldn't list the elements like we did

  • with the rational numbers. This would imply that there is more than one

  • kind of infinity.

  • To answer this question, let's talk about subsets. How many

  • subsets does the set S={a,b,c} have? Denoted by P(S), we call this the

  • power set of the original set S and we can easily list its elements.

  • To generate the subsets, it's simply a matter of noting that

  • each element is either in a subset or not, making 2^3 or 8

  • possibilities. We can do the same for other sets and note that

  • if there are n distinct objects in a set S, its power set P(S) has size 2^n.

  • Clearly the size of the power set is larger than the original set.

  • How does this relate to infinite sets? Cantor showed that

  • for ANY set S --- infinite or not --- the power set P(S) always

  • has a larger size than the original set S. This means that the power set of the positive

  • integers is uncountable, or loosely speaking, its size is a larger

  • infinity.

  • If that doesn't shock you, let's see a truly mind blowing idea,

  • but please don't watch this with small children present.

  • Let S1 represent the positive integers and S2 its power

  • set. Now let S3 be the power set of S2, an even larger infinity,

  • then let S4 be the power set of S3, a larger infinity still.

  • Of course we can keep taking power sets and thus produce a larger infinity

  • each time. This all implies a really bizarre fact:

  • there are infinitely many different kinds of infinity.

  • There's a lot more one can say about different infinities, but since

  • we have only a *finite* amount of time, let's stop here.

How can we grasp the concept of infinity? By understanding infinite sets.

字幕與單字

單字即點即查 點擊單字可以查詢單字解釋

B1 中級

什麼比無限大? (What's Bigger Than Infinity?)

  • 21 1
    簡宇謙 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日
影片單字