Placeholder Image

字幕列表 影片播放

  • Hi! I'm Jeff Pynn, and I teach philosophy[br]at Northern Illinois University.

  • In my earlier Introduction to Critical[br]Thinking video, I described the difference

  • between deductive arguments and ampliative[br]arguments.

  • In the next few videos, I'll talk a bit[br]more about each type of argument.

  • Let's start with deductive arguments.

  • An argument is a set of statements, called[br]its premises, that are meant to give you

  • a reason to believe some further statement[br]called the argument's conclusion.

  • In some arguments, the premises are meant[br]to guarantee that the conclusion is true.

  • Arguments like this are called deductive[br]arguments.

  • A good deductive argument can give you a[br]very good reason

  • for believing its conclusion.

  • After all, it guarantees that its [br]conclusion is true.

  • But not all deductive arguments are good,[br]and so there are several things to think

  • about when deciding whether to believe the[br]conclusion of a deductive argument.

  • A good deductive argument really does[br]guarantee its conclusion.

  • Part of what this means is that its[br]impossible for the premises to be true

  • while the conclusion is false.

  • When this is the case, we say that the[br]argument is valid.

  • Now this is a special, technical use of[br]the word "valid."

  • In ordinary life, we often use this word[br]to mean something like good, cogent, or

  • reasonable.

  • Like if you're disagreeing with someone[br]about something, and they respond to a

  • claim you make by saying something that[br]seems pretty reasonable to you,

  • you might say, "Well, I guess you have[br]a valid point."

  • Though that's what the word often means[br]in ordinary life,

  • it's not what the word means here.

  • When philosophers say that an argument is[br]valid, they always mean this very

  • specific thing: that if the premises are[br]true, the conclusion must also be true.

  • There are several other Wi-Phi videos that[br]discuss this notion of validity

  • in more detail.

  • To say that an argument is valid is to say[br]something about the relationship between

  • the premises and the conclusion.

  • Namely, that if the premises are true, the[br]conclusion must also be true.

  • But it's not to say that its premises or[br]conclusion are true.

  • Consider, for example, this argument.

  • Premise 1: Beyonce was born in Paris.

  • Premise 2: Everybody who was born in Paris[br]loves cheese.

  • Conclusion: Therefore, Beyonce loves[br]cheese.

  • Those premises are false. Beyonce was born[br]in Houston, and I'm willing to bet that at

  • least some people born in Paris hate[br]cheese.

  • Still, it's a valid argument.

  • If the premises were true, then the[br]conclusion would have to be true.

  • But because the premises are false, this[br]argument doesn't give you a good reason to

  • believe its conclusion, even though it's[br]valid.

  • Philosophers call a valid argument with[br]true premises "sound."

  • Like the word "valid," the word "sound" is[br]term with various meanings in ordinary

  • life, and it can be used to describe some[br]claim as reasonable or compelling.

  • But when philosophers describe an argument[br]as sound, they always mean this very

  • specific thing: that it's valid, and that[br]its premises are in fact true.

  • Here's a pretty boring sound argument.

  • Premise 1: Beyonce was born in Houston.

  • Premise 2: Everybody who was born in[br]Houston was born in Texas.

  • Conclusion: Therefore, Beyonce was born in[br]Texas.

  • For more discussion of the concept of a[br]sound argument,

  • see Aaron Ancell's Wi-Phi video entitled[br]"Soundness."

  • So, before deciding whether to believe the[br]conclusion of a deductive argument,

  • you need to determine whether the argument[br]is sound.

  • And this, in turn, requires determining[br]whether the argument is valid,

  • and whether its premises are true.

  • Well, how do you tell whether an argument[br]is valid?

  • Sometimes, it's just obvious. But often,[br]it's not so obvious.

  • One way to figure out whether an argument[br]is valid

  • is to see if you can think of a[br]counterexample to it.

  • A counterexample is a case, either real or[br]imaginary,

  • where the argument's premises are true,[br]but the conclusion is false.

  • So, for example, consider this argument.

  • Premise 1: Classical musicians appreciate[br]opera.

  • Premise 2: Beyonce is a pop star, not a[br]classical musician.

  • Conclusion: Therefore, Beyonce doesn't[br]appreciate opera.

  • Now, suppose that Beyonce's been listening[br]to opera since she was a little girl,

  • and loves Mozart's Don Giovanni.

  • Well, then she'd appreciate opera.

  • The conclusion would be false, even though[br]the premises would still be true.

  • It would still be true that classical[br]musicians appreciate opera,

  • and that Beyonce is a pop star, not a[br]classical musician.

  • This counterexample shows that the[br]argument isn't valid,

  • and so that even if premises are true, the[br]argument doesn't provide you with a reason

  • to believe its conclusion.

  • There are other, more formal techniques[br]for figuring out whether an argument is

  • valid, which we'll hopefully be able to[br]discuss in future videos.

  • Now, if you don't know whether the[br]premises of an argument are true,

  • then even if the argument really is sound,[br]it doesn't give you a good reason to

  • believe its conclusion.

  • When you know that an argument is valid,[br]but you don't know whether its premises

  • are true, the argument gives you, at best,[br]a conditional reason

  • to accept its conclusion.

  • If you learn that its premises are true,[br]then you'll have to accept its conclusion.

  • So, how do you tell whether an argument's[br]premises are true?

  • Well, this isn't the kind of thing logic[br]or philosophy can give you much help with.

  • To figure out whether an argument's[br]premises are true,

  • you need to do some research.

  • This is one reason why being a good[br]critical thinker requires more

  • than just logical ability.

  • It also takes a lot of real world,[br]empirical knowledge.

  • Unless you know enough to know whether an[br]argument's premises are true, then even if

  • you're a really brilliant logician and[br]know that the argument is valid,

  • it doesn't give you reason to believe its[br]conclusion.

  • The more you know, the better you'll be[br]able to evaluate deductive arguments.

  • Subtitles by the Amara.org community

Hi! I'm Jeff Pynn, and I teach philosophy[br]at Northern Illinois University.

字幕與單字

單字即點即查 點擊單字可以查詢單字解釋

B1 中級

批判性思維基礎。推理論證 (Critical Thinking Fundamentals: Deductive Arguments)

  • 131 18
    VoiceTube 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日
影片單字