Placeholder Image

字幕列表 影片播放

  • Structural functionalism, or simply functionalism, is a framework for building theory that sees

  • society as a complex system whose parts work together to promote solidarity and stability.

  • This approach looks at society through a macro-level orientation, which is a broad focus on the

  • social structures that shape society as a whole, and believes that society has evolved

  • like organisms. This approach looks at both social structure and social functions. Functionalism

  • addresses society as a whole in terms of the function of its constituent elements; namely

  • norms, customs, traditions, and institutions. A common analogy, popularized by Herbert Spencer,

  • presents these parts of society as "organs" that work toward the proper functioning of

  • the "body" as a whole. In the most basic terms, it simply emphasizes "the effort to impute,

  • as rigorously as possible, to each feature, custom, or practice, its effect on the functioning

  • of a supposedly stable, cohesive system". For Talcott Parsons, "structural-functionalism"

  • came to describe a particular stage in the methodological development of social science,

  • rather than a specific school of thought. The structural functionalism approach is a

  • macrosociological analysis, with a broad focus on social structures that shape society as

  • a whole.

  • Theory Classical theories are defined by a tendency

  • towards biological analogy and notions of social evolutionism:

  • Functionalist thought, from Comte onwards, has looked particularly towards biology as

  • the science providing the closest and most compatible model for social science. Biology

  • has been taken to provide a guide to conceptualizing the structure and the function of social systems

  • and to analyzing processes of evolution via mechanisms of adaptation ... functionalism

  • strongly emphasises the pre-eminence of the social world over its individual parts.

  • While one may regard functionalism as a logical extension of the organic analogies for societies

  • presented by political philosophers such as Rousseau, sociology draws firmer attention

  • to those institutions unique to industrialized capitalist society. Functionalism also has

  • an anthropological basis in the work of theorists such as Marcel Mauss, Bronisław Malinowski

  • and Radcliffe-Brown. It is in Radcliffe-Brown's specific usage that the prefix 'structural'

  • emerged. Radcliffe-Brown proposed that most stateless, "primitive" societies, lacking

  • strong centralised institutions, are based on an association of corporate-descent groups.

  • Structural functionalism also took on Malinowski's argument that the basic building block of

  • society is the nuclear family, and that the clan is an outgrowth, not vice versa.

  • Émile Durkheim was concerned with the question of how certain societies maintain internal

  • stability and survive over time. He proposed that such societies tend to be segmented,

  • with equivalent parts held together by shared values, common symbols or, as his nephew Marcel

  • Mauss held, systems of exchanges. Durkheim used the term 'mechanical solidarity' to refer

  • to these types of "social bonds, based on common sentiments & shared moral values, that

  • are strong among members of pre-industrial societies". In modern, complex societies,

  • members perform very different tasks, resulting in a strong interdependence. Based on the

  • metaphor above of an organism in which many parts function together to sustain the whole,

  • Durkheim argued that complex societies are held together by organic solidarity, i.e.

  • "social bonds, based on specialization and interdependence, that are strong among members

  • of industrial societies". These views were upheld by Durkheim, who,

  • following Comte, believed that society constitutes a separate "level" of reality, distinct from

  • both biological and inorganic matter. Explanations of social phenomena had therefore to be constructed

  • within this level, individuals being merely transient occupants of comparatively stable

  • social roles. The central concern of structural functionalism is a continuation of the Durkheimian

  • task of explaining the apparent stability and internal cohesion needed by societies

  • to endure over time. Societies are seen as coherent, bounded and fundamentally relational

  • constructs that function like organisms, with their various working together in an unconscious,

  • quasi-automatic fashion toward achieving an overall social equilibrium. All social and

  • cultural phenomena are therefore seen as functional in the sense of working together, and are

  • effectively deemed to have "lives" of their own. They are primarily analyzed in terms

  • of this function. The individual is significant not in and of himself, but rather in terms

  • of his status, his position in patterns of social relations, and the behaviours associated

  • with his status. Therefore, the social structure is the network of statuses connected by associated

  • roles. It is simplistic to equate the perspective

  • directly with political conservatism. The tendency to emphasise "cohesive systems",

  • however, leads functionalist theories to be contrasted with "conflict theories" which

  • instead emphasize social problems and inequalities. Prominent theorists

  • Auguste Comte Auguste Comte, the "Father of Positivism",

  • pointed out the need to keep society unified as many traditions were diminishing. He was

  • the first person to coin the term sociology. Auguste Comte suggests that sociology is the

  • product of a three-stage development. 1. Theological Stage: From the beginning of

  • human history until the end of the European Middle Ages, people took a religious view

  • that society expressed God's will. In the theological state, the human mind, seeking

  • the essential nature of beings, the first and final causes of all effectsin short,

  • absolute knowledgesupposes all phenomena to be produced by the immediate action of

  • supernatural beings. 2. Metaphysical Stage: People began seeing

  • society as a natural system as opposed to the supernatural. Began with the Enlightenment

  • and the ideas of Hobbes, Locke,and Rousseau. Reflected the failings of a selfish human

  • nature rather than the perfection of God. 3. Scientific Stage: Describing society through

  • the application of the scientific approach, which draws on the work of scientists.

  • Herbert Spencer

  • Herbert Spencer was a British philosopher famous for applying the theory of natural

  • selection to society. He was in many ways the first true sociological functionalist.

  • In fact, while Durkheim is widely considered the most important functionalist among positivist

  • theorists, it is well known that much of his analysis was culled from reading Spencer's

  • work, especially his Principles of Sociology. Spencer allude society to the analogy of human

  • body. Just as the structural parts of the human body - the skeleton, muscles, and various

  • internal organs - function independently to help the entire organism survive, social structures

  • work together to preserve society. While most avoid the tedious tasks of reading

  • Spencer's massive volumes, there are some important insights that have quietly influenced

  • many contemporary theorists, including Talcott Parsons, in his early work The Structure of

  • Social Action. Cultural anthropology also consistently uses functionalism.

  • This evolutionary model, unlike most 19th century evolutionary theories, is cyclical,

  • beginning with the differentiation and increasing complication of an organic or "super-organic"

  • body, followed by a fluctuating state of equilibrium and disequilibrium, and, finally, the stage

  • of disintegration or dissolution. Following Thomas Malthus' population principles, Spencer

  • concluded that society is constantly facing selection pressures that force it to adapt

  • its internal structure through differentiation. Every solution, however, causes a new set

  • of selection pressures that threaten society's viability. It should be noted that Spencer

  • was not a determinist in the sense that he never said that

  • Selection pressures will be felt in time to change them;

  • They will be felt and reacted to; or The solutions will always work.

  • In fact, he was in many ways a political sociologist, and recognized that the degree of centralized

  • and consolidated authority in a given polity could make or break its ability to adapt.

  • In other words, he saw a general trend towards the centralization of power as leading to

  • stagnation and ultimately, pressures to decentralize. More specifically, Spencer recognized three

  • functional needs or prerequisites that produce selection pressures: they are regulatory,

  • operative and distributive. He argued that all societies need to solve problems of control

  • and coordination, production of goods, services and ideas, and, finally, to find ways of distributing

  • these resources. Initially, in tribal societies, these three

  • needs are inseparable, and the kinship system is the dominant structure that satisfies them.

  • As many scholars have noted, all institutions are subsumed under kinship organization, but,

  • with increasing population, problems emerge with regard to feeding individuals, creating

  • new forms of organizationconsider the emergent division of labourcoordinating and controlling

  • various differentiated social units, and developing systems of resource distribution.

  • The solution, as Spencer sees it, is to differentiate structures to fulfill more specialized functions;

  • thus a chief or "big man" emerges, soon followed by a group of lieutenants, and later kings

  • and administrators. The structural parts of society function interdependently to help

  • society function. Therefore, social structures work together to preserve society.

  • Perhaps Spencer's greatest obstacle that is being widely discussed in modern sociology

  • is the fact that much of his social philosophy is rooted in the social and historical context

  • of Ancient Egypt. He coined the term "survival of the fittest" in discussing the simple fact

  • that small tribes or societies tend to be defeated or conquered by larger ones. Of course,

  • many sociologists still use him in their analyses, especially due to the recent re-emergence

  • of evolutionary theory. Talcott Parsons

  • Talcott Parsons was heavily influenced by Émile Durkheim and Max Weber, synthesizing

  • much of their work into his action theory, which he based on the system-theoretical concept

  • and the methodological principle of voluntary action. He held that "the social system is

  • made up of the actions of individuals." His starting point, accordingly, is the interaction

  • between two individuals faced with a variety of choices about how they might act, choices

  • that are influenced and constrained by a number of physical and social factors.

  • Parsons determined that each individual has expectations of the other's action and reaction

  • to his own behaviour, and that these expectations would be "derived" from the accepted norms

  • and values of the society they inhabit. As Parsons himself emphasized, in a general context

  • there would never exist any perfect "fit" between behaviours and norms, so such a relation

  • is never complete or "perfect." Social norms were always problematic for Parsons,

  • who never claimed that social norms were generally accepted and agreed upon, should this prevent

  • some kind of universal law. Whether social norms were accepted or not was for Parsons

  • simply a historical question. As behaviours are repeated in more interactions,

  • and these expectations are entrenched or institutionalized, a role is created. Parsons defines a "role"

  • as the normatively-regulated participation "of a person in a concrete process of social

  • interaction with specific, concrete role-partners." Although any individual, theoretically, can

  • fulfill any role, the individual is expected to conform to the norms governing the nature

  • of the role they fulfill. Furthermore, one person can and does fulfill

  • many different roles at the same time. In one sense, an individual can be seen to be

  • a "composition" of the roles he inhabits. Certainly, today, when asked to describe themselves,

  • most people would answer with reference to their societal roles.

  • Parsons later developed the idea of roles into collectivities of roles that complement

  • each other in fulfilling functions for society. Some roles are bound up in institutions and

  • social structures. These are functional in the sense that they assist society in operating

  • and fulfilling its functional needs so that society runs smoothly.

  • Contrary to prevailing myth, Parsons never spoke about a society where there was no conflict

  • or some kind of "perfect" equilibrium. A society's cultural value-system was in the typical case

  • never completely integrated, never static and most of the time, like in the case of

  • the American society in a complex state of transformation relative to its historical

  • point of departure. To reach a "perfect" equilibrium was not any serious theoretical question in

  • Parsons analysis of social systems, indeed, the most dynamic societies had generally cultural

  • systems with important inner tensions like the US and India. These tensions were a source

  • of their strength according to Parsons rather than the opposite. Parsons never thought about

  • system-institutionalization and the level of strains in the system as opposite forces

  • per se. The key processes for Parsons for system reproduction

  • are socialization and social control. Socialization is important because it is the mechanism for

  • transferring the accepted norms and values of society to the individuals within the system.

  • Parsons never spoke about "perfect socialization"—in any society socialization was only partial

  • and "incomplete" from an integral point of view.

  • Parsons states that "this point [...] is independent of the sense in which [the] individual is

  • concretely autonomous or creative rather than 'passive' or 'conforming', for individuality

  • and creativity, are to a considerable extent, phenomena of the institutionalization of expectations";

  • they are culturally constructed. Socialization is supported by the positive

  • and negative sanctioning of role behaviours that do or do not meet these expectations.

  • A punishment could be informal, like a snigger or gossip, or more formalized, through institutions

  • such as prisons and mental homes. If these two processes were perfect, society would

  • become static and unchanging, but in reality this is unlikely to occur for long.

  • Parsons recognizes this, stating that he treats "the structure of the system as problematic

  • and subject to change," and that his concept of the tendency towards equilibrium "does

  • not imply the empirical dominance of stability over change." He does, however, believe that

  • these changes occur in a relatively smooth way.

  • Individuals in interaction with changing situations adapt through a process of "role bargaining."

  • Once the roles are established, they create norms that guide further action and are thus

  • institutionalised, creating stability across social interactions. Where the adaptation

  • process cannot adjust, due to sharp shocks or immediate radical change, structural dissolution

  • occurs and either new structures are formed, or society dies. This model of social change

  • has been described as a "moving equilibrium," and emphasises a desire for social order.

  • Davis and Moore Kingsley Davis and Wilbert E. Moore gave an

  • argument for social stratification based on the idea of "functional necessity". They argue

  • that the most difficult jobs in any society have the highest incomes in order to motivate

  • individuals to fill the roles needed by the division of labour. Thus inequality serves

  • social stability. This argument has been criticized as fallacious

  • from a number of different angles: the argument is both that the individuals who are the most

  • deserving are the highest rewarded, and that a system of unequal rewards is necessary,

  • otherwise no individuals would perform as needed for the society to function. The problem

  • is that these rewards are supposed to be based upon objective merit, rather than subjective

  • "motivations." The argument also does not clearly establish why some positions are worth

  • more than others, even when they benefit more people in society, e.g., teachers compared

  • to athletes and movie stars. Critics have suggested that structural inequality is itself

  • a cause of individual success or failure, not a consequence of it.

  • Robert Merton Robert K. Merton made important refinements

  • to functionalist thought. He fundamentally agreed with Parsons' theory. However, he acknowledged

  • that it was problematic, believing that it was over generalized [Holmwood, 2005:100].

  • Merton tended to emphasize middle range theory rather than a grand theory, meaning that he

  • was able to deal specifically with some of the limitations in Parsons' theory. Merton

  • believed that any social structure probably has many functions, some more obvious than

  • others. He identified 3 main limitations: functional unity, universal functionalism

  • and indispensability [Ritzer in Gingrich, 1999]. He also developed the concept of deviance

  • and made the distinction between manifest and latent functions. Manifest functions referred

  • to the recognized and intended consequences of any social pattern. Latent functions referred

  • to unrecognized and unintended consequences of any social pattern.

  • Merton criticized functional unity, saying that not all parts of a modern complex society

  • work for the functional unity of society. Consequently, there is a social dysfunction

  • referred to as any social pattern that may disrupt the operation of society. Some institutions

  • and structures may have other functions, and some may even be generally dysfunctional,

  • or be functional for some while being dysfunctional for others. This is because not all structures

  • are functional for society as a whole. Some practices are only functional for a dominant

  • individual or a group [Holmwood, 2005:91]. There are two types of functions that Merton

  • discusses the "manifest functions" in that a social pattern can trigger a recognized

  • and intended consequence. The manifest function of education includes preparing for a career

  • by getting good grades, graduation and finding good job. The second type of function is "latent

  • functions", where a social pattern results in an unrecognized or unintended consequence.

  • The latent functions of education include meeting new people, extra-curricular activities,

  • school trips. Another type of social function is "social dysfunction" which is any undesirable

  • consequences that disrupts the operation of society. The social dysfunction of education

  • includes not getting good grades, a job. Merton states that by recognizing and examining the

  • dysfunctional aspects of society we can explain the development and persistence of alternatives.

  • Thus, as Holmwood states, "Merton explicitly made power and conflict central issues for

  • research within a functionalist paradigm" [2005:91].

  • Merton also noted that there may be functional alternatives to the institutions and structures

  • currently fulfilling the functions of society. This means that the institutions that currently

  • exist are not indispensable to society. Merton states "just as the same item may have multiple

  • functions, so may the same function be diversely fulfilled by alternative items" [cited in

  • Holmwood, 2005:91]. This notion of functional alternatives is important because it reduces

  • the tendency of functionalism to imply approval of the status quo.

  • Merton's theory of deviance is derived from Durkheim's idea of anomie. It is central in

  • explaining how internal changes can occur in a system. For Merton, anomie means a discontinuity

  • between cultural goals and the accepted methods available for reaching them.

  • Merton believes that there are 5 situations facing an actor.

  • Conformity occurs when an individual has the means and desire to achieve the cultural goals

  • socialised into him. Innovation occurs when an individual strives

  • to attain the accepted cultural goals but chooses to do so in novel or unaccepted method.

  • Ritualism occurs when an individual continues to do things as proscribed by society but

  • forfeits the achievement of the goals. Retreatism is the rejection of both the means

  • and the goals of society. Rebellion is a combination of the rejection

  • of societal goals and means and a substitution of other goals and means.

  • Thus it can be seen that change can occur internally in society through either innovation

  • or rebellion. It is true that society will attempt to control these individuals and negate

  • the changes, but as the innovation or rebellion builds momentum, society will eventually adapt

  • or face dissolution. Almond and Powell

  • In the 1970s, political scientists Gabriel Almond and Bingham Powell introduced a structural-functionalist

  • approach to comparing political systems. They argued that, in order to understand a political

  • system, it is necessary to understand not only its institutions but also their respective

  • functions. They also insisted that these institutions, to be properly understood, must be placed

  • in a meaningful and dynamic historical context. This idea stood in marked contrast to prevalent

  • approaches in the field of comparative politicsthe state-society theory and the dependency theory.

  • These were the descendants of David Easton's system theory in international relations,

  • a mechanistic view that saw all political systems as essentially the same, subject to

  • the same laws of "stimulus and response"—or inputs and outputswhile paying little attention

  • to unique characteristics. The structural-functional approach is based on the view that a political

  • system is made up of several key components, including interest groups, political parties

  • and branches of government. In addition to structures, Almond and Powell

  • showed that a political system consists of various functions, chief among them political

  • socialization, recruitment and communication: socialization refers to the way in which societies

  • pass along their values and beliefs to succeeding generations, and in political terms describe

  • the process by which a society inculcates civic virtues, or the habits of effective

  • citizenship; recruitment denotes the process by which a political system generates interest,

  • engagement and participation from citizens; and communication refers to the way that a

  • system promulgates its values and information. Structural functionalism and unilineal descent

  • In their attempt to explain the social stability of African "primitive" stateless societies

  • where they undertook their fieldwork, Evans-Pritchard and Meyer Fortes argued that the Tallensi

  • and the Nuer were primarily organized around unilineal descent groups. Such groups are

  • characterized by common purposes, such as administering property or defending against

  • attacks; they form a permanent social structure that persists well beyond the lifespan of

  • their members. In the case of the Tallensi and the Nuer, these corporate groups were

  • based on kinship which in turn fitted into the larger structures of unilineal descent;

  • consequently Evans-Pritchard's and Fortes' model is called "descent theory". Moreover,

  • in this African context territorial divisions were aligned with lineages; descent theory

  • therefore synthesized both blood and soil as two sides of one coin. Affinal ties with

  • the parent through whom descent is not reckoned, however, are considered to be merely complementary

  • or secondary, with the reckoning of kinship through descent being considered the primary

  • organizing force of social systems. Because of its strong emphasis on unilineal descent,

  • this new kinship theory came to be called "descent theory".

  • With no delay, descent theory had found its critics. Many African tribal societies seemed

  • to fit this neat model rather well, although Africanists, such as Richards, also argued

  • that Fortes and Evans-Pritchard had deliberately downplayed internal contradictions and overemphasized

  • the stability of the local lineage systems and their significance for the organization

  • of society. However, in many Asian settings the problems were even more obvious. In Papua

  • New Guinea, the local patrilineal descent groups were fragmented and contained large

  • amounts of non-agnates. Status distinctions did not depend on descent, and genealogies

  • were too short to account for social solidarity through identification with a common ancestor.

  • In particular, the phenomenon of cognatic kinship posed a serious problem to the proposition

  • that descent groups are the primary element behind the social structures of "primitive"

  • societies. Leach's critique came in the form of the classical

  • Malinowskian argument, pointing out that "in Evans-Pritchard's studies of the Nuer and

  • also in Fortes's studies of the Tallensi unilineal descent turns out to be largely an ideal concept

  • to which the empirical facts are only adapted by means of fictions.". People's self-interest,

  • manoeuvring, manipulation and competition had been ignored. Moreover, descent theory

  • neglected the significance of marriage and affinal ties, which were emphasised by Levi-Strauss'

  • structural anthropology, at the expense of overemphasising the role of descent. To quote

  • Leach: "The evident importance attached to matrilateral and affinal kinship connections

  • is not so much explained as explained away." Decline of functionalism

  • Structural functionalism reached the peak of its influence in the 1940s and 1950s, and

  • by the 1960s was in rapid decline. By the 1980s, its place was taken in Europe by more

  • conflict-oriented approaches, and more recently by 'structuralism'. While some of the critical

  • approaches also gained popularity in the United States, the mainstream of the discipline has

  • instead shifted to a myriad of empirically-oriented middle-range theories with no overarching

  • theoretical orientation. To most sociologists, functionalism is now "as dead as a dodo".

  • As the influence of both functionalism and Marxism in the 1960s began to wane, the linguistic

  • and cultural turns led to a myriad of new movements in the social sciences: "According

  • to Giddens, the orthodox consensus terminated in the late 1960s and 1970s as the middle

  • ground shared by otherwise competing perspectives gave way and was replaced by a baffling variety

  • of competing perspectives. This third 'generation' of social theory includes phenomenologically

  • inspired approaches, critical theory, ethnomethodology, symbolic interactionism, structuralism, post-structuralism,

  • and theories written in the tradition of hermeneutics and ordinary language philosophy."

  • While absent from empirical sociology, functionalist themes remained detectable in sociological

  • theory, most notably in the works of Luhmann and Giddens. There are, however, signs of

  • an incipient revival, as functionalist claims have recently been bolstered by developments

  • in multilevel selection theory and in empirical research on how groups solve social dilemmas.

  • Recent developments in evolutionary theoryespecially by biologist David Sloan Wilson and anthropologists

  • Robert Boyd and Peter Richersonhave provided strong support for structural functionalism

  • in the form of multilevel selection theory. In this theory, culture and social structure

  • are seen as a Darwinian adaptation at the group level.

  • Criticisms

  • In the 1960s, functionalism was criticized for being unable to account for social change,

  • or for structural contradictions and conflict. Also, it ignores inequalities including race,

  • gender, class, which causes tension and conflict. The refutation of the second criticism of

  • functionalism, that it is static and has no concept of change, has already been articulated

  • above, concluding that while Parsons' theory allows for change, it is an orderly process

  • of change [Parsons, 1961:38], a moving equilibrium. Therefore referring to Parsons' theory of

  • society as static is inaccurate. It is true that it does place emphasis on equilibrium

  • and the maintenance or quick return to social order, but this is a product of the time in

  • which Parsons was writing. Society was in upheaval and fear abounded. At the time social

  • order was crucial, and this is reflected in Parsons' tendency to promote equilibrium and

  • social order rather than social change. Furthermore, Durkheim favored a radical form

  • of guild socialism along with functionalist explanations. Also, Marxism, while acknowledging

  • social contradictions, still uses functionalist explanations. Parsons' evolutionary theory

  • describes the differentiation and reintegration systems and subsystems and thus at least temporary

  • conflict before reintegration. "The fact that functional analysis can be seen by some as

  • inherently conservative and by others as inherently radical suggests that it may be inherently

  • neither one nor the other." Stronger criticisms include the epistemological

  • argument that functionalism is tautologous, that is it attempts to account for the development

  • of social institutions solely through recourse to the effects that are attributed to them

  • and thereby explains the two circularly. However, Parsons drew directly on many of Durkheim's

  • concepts in creating his theory. Certainly Durkheim was one of the first theorists to

  • explain a phenomenon with reference to the function it served for society. He said, "the

  • determination of function isnecessary for the complete explanation of the phenomena"

  • [cited in Coser, 1977:140]. However Durkheim made a clear distinction between historical

  • and functional analysis, saying, "When ... the explanation of a social phenomenon is undertaken,

  • we must seek separately the efficient cause which produces it and the function it fulfills"

  • [cited in Coser, 1977:140]. If Durkheim made this distinction, then it is unlikely that

  • Parsons did not. However Merton does explicitly state that functional analysis does not seek

  • to explain why the action happened in the first instance, but why it continues or is

  • reproduced. He says that "latent functions ... go far towards explaining the continuance

  • of the pattern" [cited in Elster, 1990:130, emphasis added]. Therefore it can be argued

  • that functionalism does not explain the original cause of a phenomenon with reference to its

  • effect, and is therefore, not teleological. Another criticism describes the ontological

  • argument that society cannot have "needs" as a human being does, and even if society

  • does have needs they need not be met. Anthony Giddens argues that functionalist explanations

  • may all be rewritten as historical accounts of individual human actions and consequences.

  • A further criticism directed at functionalism is that it contains no sense of agency, that

  • individuals are seen as puppets, acting as their role requires. Yet Holmwood states that

  • the most sophisticated forms of functionalism are based on "a highly developed concept of

  • action" [2005:107], and as was explained above, Parsons took as his starting point the individual

  • and their actions. His theory did not however articulate how these actors exercise their

  • agency in opposition to the socialization and inculcation of accepted norms. As has

  • been shown above, Merton addressed this limitation through his concept of deviance, and so it

  • can be seen that functionalism allows for agency. It cannot, however, explain why individuals

  • choose to accept or reject the accepted norms, why and in what circumstances they choose

  • to exercise their agency, and this does remain a considerable limitation of the theory.

  • Further criticisms have been leveled at functionalism by proponents of other social theories, particularly

  • conflict theorists, Marxists, feminists and postmodernists. Conflict theorists criticised

  • functionalism's concept of systems as giving far too much weight to integration and consensus,

  • and neglecting independence and conflict [Holmwood, 2005:100]. Lockwood [in Holmwood, 2005:101],

  • in line with conflict theory, suggested that Parsons' theory missed the concept of system

  • contradiction. He did not account for those parts of the system that might have tendencies

  • to Mal-integration. According to Lockwood, it was these tendencies that come to the surface

  • as opposition and conflict among actors. However Parsons thought that the issues of conflict

  • and cooperation were very much intertwined and sought to account for both in his model

  • [Holmwood, 2005:103]. In this however he was limited by his analysis of an 'ideal type'

  • of society which was characterized by consensus. Merton, through his critique of functional

  • unity, introduced into functionalism an explicit analysis of tension and conflict.

  • Marxism which was revived soon after the emergence of conflict theory, criticized professional

  • sociology for being partisan to advanced welfare capitalism [Holmwood, 2005:103]. Gouldner

  • [in Holmwood, 2005:103] thought that Parsons' theory specifically was an expression of the

  • dominant interests of welfare capitalism, that it justified institutions with reference

  • to the function they fulfill for society. It may be that Parsons' work implied or articulated

  • that certain institutions were necessary to fulfill the functional prerequisites of society,

  • but whether or not this is the case, Merton explicitly states that institutions are not

  • indispensable and that there are functional alternatives. That he does not identify any

  • alternatives to the current institutions does reflect a conservative bias, which as has

  • been stated before is a product of the specific time that he was writing in.

  • As functionalism's prominence was ending, feminism was on the rise, and it attempted

  • a radical criticism of functionalism. It believed that functionalism neglected the suppression

  • of women within the family structure. Holmwood [2005:103] shows, however, that Parsons did

  • in fact describe the situations where tensions and conflict existed or were about to take

  • place, even if he did not articulate those conflicts. Some feminists agree, suggesting

  • that Parsons' provided accurate descriptions of these situations. [Johnson in Holmwood,

  • 2005:103]. On the other hand, Parsons recognized that he had oversimplified his functional

  • analysis of women in relation to work and the family, and focused on the positive functions

  • of the family for society and not on its dysfunctions for women. Merton, too, although addressing

  • situations where function and dysfunction occurred simultaneously, lacked a "feminist

  • sensibility" [Holmwood, 2005:103]. Postmodernism, as a theory, is critical of

  • claims of objectivity. Therefore the idea of grand theory that can explain society in

  • all its forms is treated with skepticism at the very least. This critique is important

  • because it exposes the danger that grand theory can pose, when not seen as a limited perspective,

  • as one way of understanding society. Jeffrey Alexander sees functionalism as a

  • broad school rather than a specific method or system, such as Parsons, who is capable

  • of taking equilibrium as a reference-point rather than assumption and treats structural

  • differentiation as a major form of social change. "The name 'functionalism' implies

  • a difference of method or interpretation that does not exist." This removes the determinism

  • criticized above. Cohen argues that rather than needs a society has dispositional facts:

  • features of the social environment that support the existence of particular social institutions

  • but do not cause them. Influential theorists

  • Kingsley Davis Michael Denton

  • Émile Durkheim David Keen

  • Niklas Luhmann Bronisław Malinowski

  • Robert K. Merton Wilbert E. Moore

  • George Murdock Talcott Parsons

  • Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown Herbert Spencer

  • Fei Xiaotong See also

  • Notes

  • References Barnard, A. 2000. History and Theory in Anthropology.

  • Cambridge: CUP. Barnard, A., and Good, A. 1984. Research Practices

  • in the Study of Kinship. London: Academic Press.

  • Barnes, J. 1971. Three Styles in the Study of Kinship. London: Butler & Tanner.

  • Holy, L. 1996. Anthropological Perspectives on Kinship. London: Pluto Press.

  • Kuper, A. 1988. The Invention of Primitive Society: Transformations of an Illusion. London:

  • Routledge. Kuper, A. 1996. Anthropology and Anthropologists.

  • London: Routledge. Layton, R. 1997. An Introduction to Theory

  • in Anthropology. Cambridge: CUP. Leach, E. 1954. Political Systems of Highland

  • Burma. London: Bell. Leach, E. 1966. Rethinking Anthropology. Northampton:

  • Dickens. Levi-Strauss, C. 1969. The Elementary Structures

  • of Kinship. London: Eyre and Spottis-woode. Coser, L., Masters of Sociological Thought:

  • Ideas in Historical and Social Context. 2nd Ed., Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich,

  • Inc., pp. 140–143. Craib, I., Modern Social Theory: From Parsons

  • to Habermas, Harvester Wheatsheaf, London Cuff, E. & Payne, G.,(eds) Perspectives in

  • Sociology, Allen & Unwin, London Davis, K. "The Myth of Functional Analysis

  • as a Special Method in Sociology and Anthropology", American Sociological Review, 24(6), 757-772.

  • Elster, J.,, “Merton's Functionalism and the Unintended Consequences of Action”,

  • in Clark, J., Modgil, C. & Modgil, S., Robert Merton: Consensus and Controversy, Falmer

  • Press, London, pp. 129–35 Gingrich, P., “Functionalism and Parsons

  • in Sociology 250 Subject Notes, University of Regina, accessed, 2406, uregina.ca

  • Holmwood, J., “Functionalism and its Criticsin Harrington, A., Modern Social Theory: an

  • introduction, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 87–109

  • Homans, George Casper. Sentiments and Activities. New York: The Free Press of Glencoe.

  • Hoult, Thomas Ford. Dictionary of Modern Sociology. Lenski, Gerhard. "Power and Privilege: A Theory

  • of Social Stratification." New York: McGraw-Hill. Lenski, Gerhard. "Evolutionary-Ecological

  • Theory." Boulder, CO: Paradigm. Maryanski, Alexandra. "Evolutionary Sociology."

  • Advances in Human Ecology. 7:1-56. Maryanski, Alexandra and Jonathan Turner.

  • "The Social Cage: Human Nature and the Evolution of Society." Stanford: Stanford University

  • Press. Marshall, Gordon. The Concise Oxford Dictionary

  • of Sociology. ISBN 0-19-285237-X Merton, Robert. Social Theory and Social Structure,

  • revised and enlarged. London: The Free Press of Glencoe.

  • Nolan, Patrick and Gerhard Lenski. Human Societies: An Introduction to Macrosociology." Boulder,

  • CO: Paradigm. Parsons, Talcott The Social System, Routledge,

  • London Parsons, T., & Shils, A., Toward a General

  • Theory of Action, Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Parsons, T., Theories of Society: foundations of modern sociological theory, Free Press,

  • New York Perey, Arnold "Malinowski, His Diary, and

  • Men Today Ritzer, G., Sociological Theory, Knopf Inc,

  • New York Sanderson, Stephen K.. "Social Transformations:

  • A General Theory of Historical Development." Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Turner, Jonathan. "Herbert Spencer: A Renewed Appreciation." Beverly Hills: Sage.

  • Turner, Jonathan. "Macrodynamics: Toward a Theory on the Organization of Human Populations."

  • New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. Turner, Jonathan and Jan Stets. "The Sociology

  • of Emotions." Cambridge. Cambridge University Press.

Structural functionalism, or simply functionalism, is a framework for building theory that sees

字幕與單字

單字即點即查 點擊單字可以查詢單字解釋

B2 中高級 英國腔

結構功能主義 (Structural functionalism)

  • 101 5
    黃柏鈞 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日
影片單字