Placeholder Image

字幕列表 影片播放

  • Professor Shelly Kagan: We've been working our way

  • through Plato's arguments for the immortality of the soul.

  • And last time I spent a fair bit of time working through

  • objections to, not quite the last argument

  • we're going to look at, but the penultimate argument,

  • in which Plato tries to argue for the simplicity of the soul.

  • The set of connected ideas, you'll recall,

  • were these: that Plato wants to suggest that in order to be

  • destroyed you've got to have parts;

  • to destroy something is to basically take its parts apart.

  • If he could only convince us that the soul was simple,

  • it would follow that it was indestructible and,

  • hence, immortal. He asks, what's our evidence

  • for some things being indestructible?

  • What kinds of things are simple? Well, these are--he then goes

  • on to claim--invisible things, things that don't change.

  • After all, changing is a matter of the rearrangement of the

  • parts. And so, if something can

  • change, it can't be simple. Maybe it could be destroyed.

  • But if we could become convinced that the soul was not

  • composite, if it was something that couldn't change,

  • then it would simple. Perhaps then it would

  • indestructible. And then he goes on to suggest

  • that the invisibility of the soul is evidence for it's being

  • changeless, and hence simple, and hence indestructible.

  • So that's the argument we worked through last time.

  • And I spent a fair bit of time suggesting that if you pin down

  • precisely what Plato means by invisible, the argument doesn't

  • actually go through. Before leaving that argument,

  • there are a couple of extra remarks I want to make about it.

  • First, we probably shouldn't have been so quick to want to

  • buy into the suggestion that the soul is changeless.

  • After all, if you think about it, it seems that at least on

  • the face of it the soul does indeed change.

  • On one day you believe, for example,

  • that it's hot; on another day you believe that

  • it's cold. On one day you believe that so

  • and so is a nice person; on the next day you believe

  • that so and so is a mean person. You desire to learn the piano,

  • the next day you give up on that desire.

  • Your beliefs, your goals, your intentions,

  • your desires--these things are all constantly changing.

  • And so, at least on the face of it, it looks as though we might

  • well want to say the soul--if we do believe there are souls--the

  • soul is changing as well, in terms of what thoughts and

  • beliefs it's housing. So we should have been

  • skeptical in the first place of any argument that said,

  • based on the invisibility of the soul, we can conclude that

  • it's changeless. It doesn't seem to be in fact

  • changeless. Furthermore,

  • we should be, or at least we might well be,

  • skeptical of the claim that the soul is simple.

  • Indeed, Plato himself, in other dialogues,

  • argues against the simplicity of the soul.

  • Now, that doesn't mean he's right in the other dialogues,

  • but at least suggests that we shouldn't be so ready to assume

  • that sort of position is correct.

  • In The Republic, famously, Plato goes on to

  • argue that the soul has at least three different parts.

  • There's a rational part that's in charge of reasoning;

  • there's a spirited part that's sort of like the will;

  • there's a part that has to do with appetite,

  • desires for food, drink, sex, what have you.

  • Plato elsewhere argues the soul is not simple at all.

  • So perhaps it shouldn't shock us that the argument he's

  • sketching here for the simplicity of the soul based on

  • the changeless, invisible nature of the

  • soul--perhaps it shouldn't shock us that that argument doesn't

  • succeed after all. Finally, although I gave Plato,

  • previously, the assumption that if only we could establish the

  • simplicity of the soul, it would follow that soul was

  • indestructible--after all, you couldn't break a soul by

  • tearing its pieces apart if it didn't have pieces,

  • if it didn't have parts--nonetheless,

  • I just want to register the thought that it's not actually

  • obvious that simples can't be destroyed.

  • Well, they clearly can't be destroyed by the particular

  • method of destruction that involves taking them apart.

  • If they don't have parts, you can't take them apart.

  • But for all that, it still seems conceptually

  • possible for a simple to be destroyed in the following

  • sense: it goes out of existence. After all, where did the

  • simples come from in the first place?

  • Well, at least from a logical point of view,

  • it seems as though there's no difficulty in imagining that at

  • one point a given simple didn't exist and then at the next point

  • it popped into existence. Well, how did that happen?

  • Maybe God said--God says at the beginning of Genesis,

  • "Let there be light." So maybe He says,

  • "Let there be simples." At a given moment they weren't

  • there; the next moment they were.

  • Well, after a while maybe God says, "Let the simples no longer

  • exist." Given moment there they were;

  • the next moment, they no longer exist.

  • Seems as though that idea makes sense, and so even if we agreed

  • that the soul was simple, even if we granted everything

  • in Plato's argument up to this point and said,

  • "the soul really is simple," it still wouldn't follow that it's

  • immortal. We'd still have to worry about

  • the possibility that the simple soul might simply pop out of

  • existence at a given point, perhaps the very point when the

  • body gets destroyed. So I'm inclined to think that

  • this most recent argument of Plato's--the argument from

  • simplicity--no, that's not successful either.

  • Before leaving that argument, there's one other piece

  • of business I want to discuss. This is a footnote that I put

  • aside, a point that I put aside previously.

  • You'll recall that we were worried about--The objection got

  • raised the right way to think about the soul is like the

  • harmony of a harp. And this was originally offered

  • as a counterexample to the thought that invisible things

  • couldn't be destroyed. But harmony could be destroyed.

  • It was invisible, so invisible things could be

  • destroyed. But I noticed,

  • I mentioned that, look, whether or not this is a

  • problem for the argument, it's an interesting suggestion

  • in its own right. Because the suggestion that the

  • mind is to the body, the soul is to the body,

  • like harmony is to an instrument with strings,

  • seems to me to be an early attempt to describe something

  • like the physicalist conception of the mind.

  • Just as harmony is something that gets produced by a

  • well-tuned instrument, the soul or the mind is

  • something that gets produced by a well-tuned body.

  • Now Plato's got some objections to the suggestion that we should

  • think of the mind as the harmony of the body.

  • And so I want to take just a moment and talk about those

  • objections because, of course, if they were

  • compelling objections that might well give us reason to doubt the

  • physicalist view. Whether or not Plato's

  • arguments for the immortality of the soul work,

  • he might still have some good arguments against the

  • physicalist conception. But in thinking about these

  • objections, it's important to bear in mind that it's only

  • meant--the harmony analogy is only meant--as just that,

  • as an analogy. Right?

  • The claim isn't, or at least it shouldn't be,

  • understood as saying literally, "the mind is harmony."

  • It's rather, the mind is like

  • harmony; it's the sort of thing to the

  • body like harmony is to a harp, something that can be produced

  • by a well-functioning, well-tuned physical object.

  • A well-tuned instrument can produce melody and harmony.

  • A well-tuned, properly functioning body can

  • produce mental activity. That's the suggestion.

  • And so even if it turns out that there are some ways in

  • which the mind isn't exactly like harmony,

  • it doesn't show us that the physicalist view is wrong.

  • Well, so let's quickly look at what Plato's arguments were.

  • First--this is, I think, an interesting

  • argument--Plato says, harmony clearly cannot exist

  • before the existence of the harp itself.

  • Right? The melodiousness of the harp

  • can't exist prior to the physical construction of the

  • harp. And if mind were the sort of

  • thing that was produced by the proper functioning of the

  • physical body, then pretty obviously the mind

  • could not exist prior to the creation of the physical body.

  • However, Plato has already argued earlier in the dialogue

  • that the soul does exist prior to the existence of the body.

  • That's the argument from recollection.

  • If the soul exists prior to the body, it can't be like harmony;

  • physicalism has clearly got to be false.

  • But I said that I didn't find the argument--I tried to explain

  • why I didn't find the argument from recollection persuasive.

  • I certainly do want to agree that if we became convinced that

  • the soul did exist prior to the existence of the body,

  • we would certainly want to agree that the soul is not like

  • harmony. But I don't think the argument

  • from recollection succeeds.

  • Plato's second objection is to point out that harmony can vary.

  • We talk about the melodiousness of the harp.

  • Well, it could be harmonious in a variety of different ways and,

  • indeed, to different degrees.

  • Something--an instrument--could be more or less harmonious.

  • What it's playing can be in greater or lesser harmony.

  • But it doesn't seem as though souls come in degrees.

  • You've got a soul or you don't have a soul.

  • That's the argument, that's the objection.

  • You've got a mind or you don't have a mind.

  • But perhaps we should--That's the objection,

  • and of course if that was right then again we might have to

  • conclude, well, whatever the mind is,

  • it's not quite like harmony is to the body.

  • But I'm not so sure we should agree that the mind can't come

  • in degrees. It can at least--The mental

  • aspects can come in degrees. We can have varying degrees of

  • intelligence, varying degrees of creativity,

  • varying degrees of reasonableness,

  • varying degrees of ability to communicate.

  • So just as, we might say, just as the functioning of the

  • harp can come in varying degrees--more or less

  • harmony--the functioning of the body in terms of its mind can

  • come in varying degrees. So that second objection

  • doesn't seem to me very compelling.

  • Third objection, Plato points out--Socrates

  • points out--that the soul can be good or it could be evil,

  • wicked. When the soul is good,

  • when you've got somebody who has got their stuff together,

  • we might speak of them as having a harmonious soul.

  • If the soul were to the body like harmony is to the

  • instrument and the soul can be harmonious,

  • it would seem as though we'd have to be able to talk about

  • harmony being harmonious. So just as we can talk about

  • the harmony of the soul, we'd have to be able to--if the

  • soul is like the harmony of the body--we'd have to be able to

  • talk about the harmony of the harmony.

  • But we don't talk about harmony of the harmony.

  • I'm not quite sure what to make of this objection.

  • This might be a point where it would be well to remind

  • ourselves of the fact that the suggestion was never that the

  • soul just literally is harmony. It's just similar to harmony,

  • says the physicalist, in the way that harmony gets

  • produced by the body--by the instrument.

  • In that same way, mind or mental activity gets

  • produced by the body. We don't have to say that

  • everything that's true of the mind is true of harmony and

  • everything that's true of harmony is true of the body--or

  • the mind. Still, I think there's a bit

  • more we can say in response to this objection,

  • and that's this: Just as it's true that we can

  • talk about minds or souls being good or wicked,

  • we can talk about different kinds of harmony.

  • There are--Certain harmonies are sweeter than others;

  • some of them are more jarring and atonal or discordant.

  • Although we might not normally talk about how harmonious the

  • harmony is, it seems as though harmonies can come in different

  • sorts and different kinds. And then, it turns out we

  • really would have an analogy to the mind, which can come in

  • different sorts and different kinds.

  • So I think this third objection isn't really compelling either.

  • Finally, Plato raises one more objection.

  • He says, "Look, the soul is capable of

  • directing the body, bossing it around,

  • and indeed capable of opposing the body."

  • You know, your body might want that piece of chocolate cake,

  • but your soul says, "No, no.

  • You're on a diet. Don't eat it."

  • Right? Your soul can oppose the body.

  • But if the soul was just harmony of the body,

  • how could it do that? After all, the harmoniousness

  • of the harp can't affect what the harp does.

  • All the causal interaction is one way, as we might put it.

  • In the case of the harp and the musicality and the melodiousness

  • and the harmony, the physical state of the harp

  • causes the melodiousness to be the way it is.

  • But the harmoniousness of the harp, doesn't ever change or

  • alter or direct the way the physical object the harp is.

  • In contrast, not only can the body affect

  • the soul, the soul can affect the body.

  • So that suggests it can't really be like harmony and the

  • harp after all. I think that's a pretty

  • interesting objection. Since we do think,

  • at least in the kind of position that we've been taking

  • for this class, that the soul can affect the

  • body, we might ask, how could it be that it's--that

  • the physicalist view is right? If talk about the mind is just

  • a way of talking about what the body can do, how can the

  • abilities of the body affect the body itself?

  • I think the answer to this objection is probably going to

  • be something like, what's really going on when we

  • talk about the soul affecting the body is that--when we say

  • certain functions of the body are affecting the body--that

  • certain mental functions are affecting the body--how does

  • this happen causally? Well, something like the

  • physical parts of the body that underwrite, that lie beneath the

  • proper functioning, the proper mental functioning

  • of body, those are able to alter the other parts of the body.

  • So look, right now I'm telling by body, "Wiggle my fingers."

  • My soul is giving instructions to my body.

  • How does that happen? That's my mind giving

  • instructions to my body. How does that happen on the

  • physicalist view? Well, my mind giving

  • instructions to my body, "wiggle my fingers," is just

  • one part of my body, my brain, giving instructions

  • to another part of my body, the muscles in my fingers.

  • So, although we talk about the mind altering the body,

  • strictly what's going on there, says the physicalist,

  • is just one part of the body affecting another part of the

  • body. Can we have something like that

  • with a harp? Well, maybe not.

  • Right? Maybe the harp's too simple a

  • machine to have one part of it affect another part of it in

  • that way. Even if that were true,

  • that wouldn't give us reason to reject the physicalist

  • conception. It would just give us reason to

  • think the harp's not very much like the mind and the body.

  • It's just the beginnings of a picture, of a physicalist

  • picture. Still, even if we think about

  • the harp and musicality, I think we can see something

  • analogous. Suppose I pluck a string on my

  • harp, producing a certain note. As we know, the vibrations of

  • one string can set into play the other strings vibrating as well.

  • And so, suddenly, what's happening in one part of

  • the harp affects what's going on in other parts of the harp.

  • The musicality of my playing a certain chord on the harp may

  • create certain kinds of overtones in the harp,

  • setting the harp vibrating in various other ways.

  • Well, that would be analogous--perhaps not a precise

  • analogy, but at least a rough analogy to what goes on when my

  • mind affects my body--to--if one part of my body affects other

  • parts of my body. So, on the one hand,

  • I want to give Plato a fair bit of credit for taking the

  • physicalist view seriously enough to try to criticize it.

  • And since when he was writing there weren't the kind of

  • complicated thinking machines that we've got nowadays,

  • it's no criticism of Plato that he used simple machines like

  • musical instruments to try to think about what a physicalist

  • picture would look like. I want to give him credit,

  • but I also want to suggest that the objections that he raises to

  • the physicalist view just don't succeed.

  • All right. Now, there's one other argument

  • that I want to consider in our dialogue.

  • And after the appeal to the simplicity of the soul,

  • there's a very long complicated discussion about what

  • constitutes an adequate explanation,

  • and Socrates gives some of his history there and talks about

  • what he's looking for in trying to find adequate explanations of

  • things. And these passages are very,

  • very difficult and happily for our purposes we don't really

  • need to go there. Before the dialogue ends

  • though, there's one further argument, which I'll dub,

  • "the argument from essential properties."

  • Now again, it's important to bear in mind as we try to make

  • sense of this passage that Plato is writing at a time when we

  • don't have, we didn't have,

  • all the conceptual apparatus that we have nowadays.

  • We stand on his shoulders; we've inherited some of the

  • distinctions that he was the first to try to put into play.

  • And so although, again, he's about to--I'm about

  • to sketch or reconstruct an argument and claim that that the

  • argument doesn't actually work, this isn't really meant by way

  • of being dismissive of Plato. I want to give him a tremendous

  • amount of credit. He's trying to see his way

  • through a morass of issues that are still confusing to us today,

  • though I think we can see somewhat further than he was

  • able to see. At any rate,

  • the distinction we need to understand the final argument,

  • is the distinction between an essential property and a

  • contingent property. An essential property is a

  • property that a given object must have;

  • it always has as long as it exists at all.

  • A contingent property is a property that an object may

  • have, may happen to have its entire existence,

  • but could've existed without. So my car is blue.

  • That's a contingent property of my car.

  • I could take it to the paint shop and get it painted red,

  • in which case it would be red. It would no longer be blue,

  • but the car would still exist. My car is blue,

  • but it could be red; it could exist as a red car.

  • And even if I never, over the entire course of

  • existence of my car, never get it painted,

  • so that from the moment it came into creation to the moment it

  • gets smashed it's always blue--still,

  • we understand perfectly well the idea that it could've been

  • red. There's nothing incompatible

  • with the idea that this car exists and is red.

  • So that's an example of a contingent property.

  • And I might have a pencil, and the pencil is whole.

  • And I never break it, but I could've broken it.

  • That's a contingent property, whether the pencil is whole or

  • broken. I take a piece of metal;

  • it's a contingent property whether it's straight or bent.

  • I bend it; now it's bent. I might straighten it back out;

  • now it's straight. Many, many properties are

  • contingent properties. You're happy,

  • you're sad, you're awake, you're asleep.

  • But some properties, in contrast,

  • are essential properties. For the particular thing that

  • we're thinking about, it's not possible to have that

  • thing and not have the property in question.

  • Plato gives the example of fire and being hot.

  • Fire is hot. That's a property that it's

  • got, but it's not a contingent property;

  • it's an essential property. It's not as though some fire is

  • hot and some fire is cold or, "Oh yes, it just happens that

  • over the entire life of the fire the fire is hot,

  • but we could have made it cold." There's no such thing;

  • there could be no such thing as cold fire.

  • As long as you've got a bit of fire, it's hot.

  • Take away the heat, you take away the fire,

  • you destroy the fire. You can't have cold fire.

  • That's an example of an essential property.

  • That is to say, Plato sees, as indeed I take it

  • we all see at least roughly, that there's some sort of

  • distinction there, and he's trying to see his way

  • clear on these matters. That remains a controversial

  • question today--until today. Are there really essential

  • properties in the way we take there to be?

  • If so, which properties are essential?

  • Which ones are contingent? Water is composed of

  • H_2O--that's its atomic structure.

  • Is that an essential property of water?

  • Could you have something that was water without being composed

  • of H_2O--hydrogen and oxygen in that way?

  • Well, some people say yes, some people say no--but most of

  • us we want to say, "Oh, there's an example of an

  • essential property. To be water,

  • you must have that atomic structure."

  • All right. That's the thought.

  • Now, armed with this distinction, Plato says,

  • "Here's an essential property for the soul.

  • Wherever there's a soul, it's alive."

  • Now, by "alive," I take it Plato means it's thinking,

  • or it's capable of thought. Wherever you've got a soul,

  • you've got something capable of thought.

  • I suppose one could try to resist this claim of Plato's,

  • but I find it reasonably plausible.

  • I start thinking about minds, and I ask myself,

  • "Could there be a mind that was incapable of thought?"

  • Maybe not. Maybe that's just built into

  • minds by definition. Just like you couldn't have

  • something that was fire without it being hot,

  • you couldn't have something that was a mind without it being

  • capable of thought. It's important to say the word

  • capable here. Right?

  • It's not as though all minds always are thinking.

  • I presume there are stretches during the night when my mind is

  • not thinking, not dreaming.

  • Still, it's capable of thought even thought it's not thinking

  • at the time.

  • But you say, "No. Here's a mind that's not even

  • capable of thought." I want to say,

  • "Then, it's just not a mind." So all right,

  • maybe being capable of thought is an essential property of the

  • mind. Plato thinks about the mind in

  • terms of souls, so maybe being capable of

  • thought is an essential property of the soul.

  • And I think that's what Plato means when he suggests the mind

  • is essential--the soul is essentially alive.

  • It's a necessary property, as we might put it,

  • of the soul, that it's alive,

  • that it's capable of thought. So I want to say,

  • "Not an implausible claim." Let's give it to Socrates.

  • But once we give it to Socrates, Plato thinks now he's

  • pretty much done. After all, think about what it

  • means to say that something's got an essential property.

  • Fire's got the essential property of being hot.

  • It means there are only two possibilities.

  • Either you've got some fire and it will be hot,

  • or the fire has been destroyed, it's been put out.

  • Those are the only two possibilities.

  • You either have--If heat is an essential property of fire,

  • either you've got some fire and it's hot, or the fire no longer

  • exists, it's been put out. There's no third possibility of

  • a non-hot fire, of a cold fire.

  • So, if you've got the claim that life's an essential

  • property of the soul, only two possibilities:

  • either you've got the soul and it's alive--to wit,

  • it's capable of thought--or the soul's been destroyed.

  • But Plato thinks we can rule out that other possibility.

  • How? Well, it's by thinking about

  • this particular essential property.

  • There's nothing in the idea that fire has the essential

  • property of being hot to make us think it couldn't be destroyed,

  • but there is something, Plato thinks,

  • in the idea of being essentially alive to rule out

  • the possibility of its being destroyed.

  • In fact, as you say the very words you begin to feel the

  • force, the pull of Plato's position.

  • If the soul is essentially alive, if it's necessarily

  • alive, it's got to be alive. It can't be destroyed.

  • That's, I think, at least the kind of argument

  • that Plato means to put forward. He does it in terms of the

  • phrase, "deathless." He says, I want to actually get

  • this up here on the board. One--life is an essential

  • property of the soul.

  • But if you think about what that means, it follows that the

  • soul is deathless.

  • After all, if the soul is--If it's essentially alive,

  • that means it can't be dead. So it's deathless.

  • But after all, anything that's deathless can't

  • die. So the soul cannot die,

  • which is just to say it's indestructible.

  • So, soul can't be destroyed.

  • Something like this seems to be Plato's argument.

  • One, life's an essential property of the soul,

  • but we can just summarize that by saying the soul is deathless.

  • But if the soul is deathless, it can't die.

  • If it can't die, it can't be destroyed,

  • it's indestructible. So the soul can't be destroyed.

  • Remember, once we said the soul was alive, there were only two

  • possibilities. If the soul was essentially

  • alive, either we have the soul, it's alive, capable of thought,

  • or it's destroyed. But if the soul can't be

  • destroyed, that leaves only the possibility the soul is alive,

  • capable of thought. That's just what Plato thinks;

  • the soul will always exist, capable of thought.

  • Well, it won't shock you to hear that I don't think this

  • argument actually works. And I think where it goes wrong

  • is there's a certain kind of ambiguity in the idea of being

  • deathless.

  • What does it mean to say that something is deathless?

  • I think there are two possible interpretations of that phrase.

  • If something is deathless, then it can't be that--well,

  • what? One possibility is,

  • it can't be that the soul exists and is dead.

  • That's one possible interpretation.

  • To say that something is deathless means you'll never

  • have a soul that exists and the same time that it exists it's

  • dead.

  • But there's a second possible interpretation of deathless.

  • It can't be that the soul was destroyed.

  • It's very easy to confuse these two interpretations of

  • deathless, A and B. And basically,

  • this is what I think is going on with Plato.

  • He's running back and forth between these two

  • interpretations. If life is an essential

  • property of the soul, then that means we will never

  • have, as it were, a soul in our hand that exists

  • and is dead. Just in the same way that

  • you'll never have a piece of fire in your hand,

  • as it were, that exists and is cold.

  • It can't happen. Wherever you've got a soul,

  • it is alive. So it's deathless in sense

  • number, in sense A. Since wherever you've got a

  • soul it must be alive, it couldn't be the case that

  • the soul exists and is dead. So it's deathless in sense A.

  • But for all that, it could still be,

  • logically speaking, that the soul could be

  • destroyed, just like a fire can be put out.

  • We could imagine something that couldn't be destroyed.

  • Then of course it would be deathless in sense B,

  • a much stronger sense of deathless.

  • What Plato needs, what Plato wants,

  • is to convince us that the soul is deathless in sense B:

  • It's true of the soul that it can't be that it was destroyed.

  • But all he's entitled to is sense A: You'll never have a

  • soul that exists and is dead, because being alive is an

  • essential property of the soul. But the mere fact that where

  • there's a soul it's alive, doesn't mean the soul couldn't

  • be destroyed. Just like from the fact that

  • where there's fire it's hot doesn't mean the fire can't be

  • destroyed.

  • It's, I think, pretty easy to get confused in

  • thinking about these issues. It's difficult to see your way

  • clearly to these two different notions of deathless.

  • It's difficult to get to the point where you can clearly use

  • the language of essential properties without getting

  • screwed up. Still, I think that's what

  • happened here. We grant Plato the thought that

  • the soul has an essential property of being alive;

  • from this, it follows that where there's a soul it is

  • alive, and hence, it's deathless in sense A.

  • But once we start thinking about the category,

  • the notion of being deathless, we're tempted to re-understand

  • that as being deathless in sense B, can't be destroyed.

  • And that, I think, doesn't follow.

  • All right. Where does that leave us?

  • Plato's gone through a series of arguments for the

  • immortality, the indestructibility of the soul,

  • and I've argued that none of them work.

  • Some of them are worth taking seriously.

  • That's why we've spent the last week or so going over them.

  • But none of them, as far as I can see,

  • are successful. And I hardly need remind you

  • that this comes on the heels of a previous week or two in which

  • we talked about various other arguments for the very existence

  • of an immaterial soul. And I've argued that none of

  • those arguments work either. As far as I can see then,

  • the arguments that might be offered for the existence of an

  • immaterial soul, let alone an immortal soul,

  • the arguments don't succeed. It's not that the idea of a

  • soul is in any way silly; it's not that it's not worth

  • thinking about. It's that when we ask

  • ourselves, "Do we have any good reason to believe in an

  • immaterial soul?" and actually try to spell out

  • what those reasons might be, as we look more carefully we

  • see the arguments are not very compelling.

  • So I'm prepared to conclude there is no soul.

  • There's no good reason to believe in souls.

  • And I so I conclude--at least there's no good enough reason to

  • believe in souls--and so I conclude there are none.

  • And this is the position that here on out I'm going to be

  • assuming for the rest of the class.

  • I'm going to have us continue to think about death,

  • but now think about death from the physicalist perspective.

  • Given the assumption that the body is all there is,

  • that talk about the mind is just a way of talking about the

  • abilities of the body to do certain special mental

  • activities. There are no extra things

  • beyond the body, no immaterial souls.

  • Now, it wouldn't be unreasonable at this point to

  • accuse me of begging the question.

  • After all, think about what I've done.

  • I've put all of the burden of proof on the fan of souls.

  • I've asked the dualist, "Give me some reason to believe

  • your position." And I've said the arguments on

  • behalf of dualism aren't very convincing.

  • Don't I now need, in fairness,

  • to do the same thing for the physicalist?

  • Don't I need to turn to the physicalist and say,

  • "Give me some reason to believe that physicalism is true?

  • Give me some reason to believe souls don't exist."

  • After all, I turned to the dualist and said,

  • "Give me some reason to believe in souls."

  • Those arguments didn't work. Don't I now need to turn to the

  • physicalist and say, "Give me some reason not

  • to believe in souls? Prove that souls don't

  • exist." Isn't that fair?

  • So let's pause and ask ourselves, how do you go about

  • proving that something doesn't exist?

  • Or, to put it in a slightly better way, when do you need to

  • prove that something doesn't exist?

  • When we have examples of things whose existence we don't believe

  • in, how do we decide when we're justified in disbelieving them?

  • Take something like dragons. Let me assume that everybody in

  • this class, in this room, does not believe in the

  • existence of dragons.

  • How do I prove that there aren't any dragons?

  • I mean, there could be dragons. Couldn't there?

  • But there aren't any. We don't believe in dragons.

  • So don't you need to disprove the existence of dragons before

  • you continue on your way of not believing in them?

  • I imagine nobody in this room believes in the existence of

  • Zeus, the Greek god. How do you disprove the

  • existence of Zeus? Don't we have an obligation to

  • prove that Zeus doesn't exist? But how could you do that?

  • Well, unsurprisingly, I don't actually think you do

  • have an obligation to disprove those things.

  • That doesn't mean you don't have any obligations.

  • You just have to be very careful about what the

  • intellectual obligations come to.

  • So back to dragons. What do we need to do for

  • dragons? Well, the most important thing

  • you need to do, to justify your skepticism

  • about dragons, is to refute all of the

  • arguments that might be offered on behalf of dragons.

  • My son's got a book about dragons with some very nice

  • photographs. So, one of the things I need to

  • do in order to justify my skepticism about dragons is

  • explain away the photographs, or the drawings,

  • or what have you. I need to explain why it is

  • that we have pictures, even though there really aren't

  • any dragons. Well, some of these are just

  • drawings, and people were drawing things out of their

  • imagination. The things that look like

  • photographs, nowadays with computer generated graphics,

  • you can make things that look like photographs,

  • and given Photoshop you can make things that look like

  • pictures of just about anything that doesn't even exist.

  • How do I prove there aren't any unicorns?

  • Well, I look at the various reported sightings of unicorns

  • and I try to explain them away, "Well, you know,

  • it's the first time people, Europeans, saw the rhinoceros.

  • It sort of reminded them of a horse with a big horn.

  • And maybe that's where the reports of rhinoceros came--or

  • the various reports of the unicorn came from.

  • The various unicorn horns that have been offered in various

  • collections, upon examination by biologists turn out to be

  • narwhal horns, horns from whales,

  • and so forth and so on." You look at each bit of

  • evidence that gets offered on behalf of the unicorn and you

  • debunk it. You explain why it's not

  • compelling. And when you're done,

  • you're entitled to say, "You know, as far as I can

  • tell, there aren't any unicorns. As far as I can tell,

  • there aren't any dragons." It's not as though you've got

  • some obligation to look in every single cave anywhere on the

  • surface of the Earth and say, "Oh, no dragons in there,

  • no dragons in there, no dragons in there,

  • no dragons in there, no dragons in there."

  • You are pretty much justified in being skeptical about the

  • existence of dragons once you've undermined the arguments for

  • dragons. Now, there might be something

  • more that you could do. In at least some cases,

  • you can go on to argue the very idea of the kind of thing we're

  • talking about is impossible. It's not just--Take dragons

  • again; it's not just that there's no

  • good reason to believe in dragons.

  • The very idea of a dragon may be scientifically incoherent,

  • at least given the science as we understand it.

  • I mean, dragons are supposed to breath fire.

  • So that must mean they've got fire in their belly.

  • But how does the fire continue to exist in their belly,

  • absent--lack of oxygen? Why isn't the fire in their

  • belly busy burning and destroying the membranes of

  • their stomach or whatever? All right, you could,

  • I suppose, try to prove that dragons were scientifically

  • impossible.

  • And if you could, then you'd have an extra reason

  • to not believe in them. But it's not as though you have

  • to prove that something's impossible to be justified in

  • not believing in it. I don't think unicorns are

  • impossible. I just don't think there are

  • any. Surely, there could be horses

  • with a single long horn growing out of their forehead.

  • There just aren't any. So armed with these ideas,

  • come back to the discussion of souls.

  • Do I, as a physicalist who does not believe in the existence of

  • souls, immaterial entities above and beyond the body,

  • do I need to disprove the existence of souls?

  • "Well, there's no soul here, no souls there."

  • No. What I need to do is to take a

  • look at each argument that gets offered for the existence of a

  • soul and rebut it--explain why those arguments are not

  • compelling. I don't need to prove that

  • souls are impossible. I just need to undermine the

  • case for souls. If there's no good reason to

  • believe in souls, that actually constitutes a

  • reason to believe there are no souls.

  • Now, if you want to, you could go on and try to

  • prove that souls are impossible in the same way that maybe

  • dragons are impossible.

  • But I'm not sure that I myself find such impossibility claims

  • especially persuasive. I don't believe in the

  • existence of souls, but that doesn't mean that I

  • find the idea of an immaterial entity like the soul impossible.

  • Now, some people might say, "Well, you know,

  • it violates science as we know it.

  • It violates physics to have there be something immaterial."

  • But science is constantly coming around to believe in

  • entities or properties that it didn't believe in previously.

  • Maybe it just hasn't gotten around to believing in souls

  • yet. Or if current science rules out

  • the possibility of souls, maybe we should say,

  • "So much the worse for current science."

  • So I'm not somebody who wants to say we can disprove the

  • existence of souls. I don't think we can disprove

  • them. I don't think the idea of a

  • soul is in any way incoherent. There are philosophers who've

  • thought that. I'm not one of them.

  • But I don't think I need to disprove the existence of a soul

  • to be justified in not believing in it.

  • Unicorns aren't impossible, but for all that,

  • I'm justified in thinking there aren't any.

  • Why? Because all the evidence for

  • unicorns just doesn't add up to very convincing case.

  • Souls are not impossible, but for all that,

  • I think I'm justified in believing there aren't any.

  • Why? Because when you look for

  • the--look at the arguments that have been offered to try to

  • convince us of the existence of souls,

  • those arguments just aren't very compelling,

  • or so it seems to me. So, from this point on out,

  • I'll be assuming the physicalist view is correct,

  • and will be thinking about the issues of death as they'd be

  • understood from the physicalist point of view.

Professor Shelly Kagan: We've been working our way

字幕與單字

單字即點即查 點擊單字可以查詢單字解釋

B1 中級

9.柏拉圖,第四部分:靈魂不朽的論點(續)。 (9. Plato, Part IV: Arguments for the immortality of the soul (cont.))

  • 139 9
    吳詠歆 發佈於 2021 年 01 月 14 日
影片單字